Nature had become the issue. A common belief
about the Romantics is that their art suggests they prized especially
highly those moments when they were suffused with enthusiasm at Nature's
goodness, and that these moments shaped their general view of nature.
We commonly think of Romanticism as the moment of the immanentization
of the Divine, the historical moment when the Divine descends from
His transcendental status and enters the realm of nature. There is,
of course, something to this: Romantic poets from Wordsworth to Leopardi
promulgated exactly such ideas. But a closer examination reveals that
the belief system that characterized the Romantic era was much more
various and capacious than our common picture of it suggests. Romanticism
might have celebrated our oneness with the great 'I am,' it might
have hymned the harmony of the natural order, it might have extolled
the richness and fullness of life (our sense of the Fülle des Lebens),
it might have offered a pastoral idyll of blissful innocence and happy
ignorance, but it is also concerned with disease, fever, death, pallour,
La Belle Dame Sans Merci, the powers of darkness, melancholy, solitude,
exile, alienation, self-torture, self-annihilation, suicide, l'homme
fatal, and damnation. The image of nature as a realm whose dire
forces demand sacrifice is not one that we ordinarily associate with
the Romantics; yet Romantic writings on the Sublime express the view
that Nature is baleful domain. The Romantics did extol Nature as a
realm interfused with divine presence; however, they also understood
nature as being permeated by dire forces that demand sacrifice. The
root of that understanding is that Be-ing and dying are inseparable.
The ideas about the sublime that Kant put
forward in Kritik der Urteilskraft was the inspiration:
Bold,
overhanging, and as it were threatening rocks; clouds piled up in
the sky, moving with lightning flashes and thunder peals; volcanoes
in all their violence of destruction; hurricanes with their track
of devastation; the boundless ocean in a state of tumult; the lofty
waterfall of a mighty river, and such like - these exhibit our faculty
of resistance as insignificantly small in comparison with their might.
But the sight of them is the more attractive, the more fearful it
is, provided only that we are in security; and we willingly call these
objects sublime, because they raise the energies of the soul above
their accustomed height and discover in us a faculty of resistance
of a quite different kind, which gives us courage to measure ourselves
against the apparent almightiness of nature.[iii][3]
Once ensconced in a safe haven, we take pleasure
in nature's terrifying majesty, because we feel that sights invested
with such power augment our own psychic strength. Who can read this
without detecting a desperation to deny a sense of nature as dangerous
realm, permeated by dire forces? In the end, Kant suggested, nature's
omnipotence is only illusory (the "seeming omnipotence of nature,"
Kant writes), but humans are possessed of an even stronger capacity
to resist the appeal of nature's terrifying majesty than to succumb
to it. Kant's ideas were influential - he affected many of the Romantics,
including Hegel. Hegel adopted and reformulated this Kantian view
by radicalizing it; Hegel's philosophy, too, proposes that nature's
power is only illusory.
Novalis, Schelling, and Hegel all gave
voice to the belief that Nature harbours dire forces, but so did Goethe.
Here is a passage that Goethe copied into a notebook:
Nature!
We are surrounded and embraced by her - without being able to exit
from her or to enter into her more deeply. Unasked and unwarned, we
are taken up into the circuitry of her dance; she has her way with
us, until we grow weary and sink from arms. . . .
We
live in the midst of her and are foreign to her. She speaks to us
ceaselessly and does not betray her secret to us. We work our endless
effects on her, yet have no dominion over her.
She
seems to have invested all her hopes in individuality, and she cares
nothing for individuals. Always she builds, always she destroys, and
we have no access to her workshop.
She
lives in a profusion of children, and their mother, where is she?
-
She
squirts her creatures out of nothingness, and does not tell them where
they came from and where they are going. Their task is to run; hers
is to know the orbit.[iv][4]
As this passage suggests, the Romantics
believed that being owned be nature - being operated by its tumultuous,
ceaselessly striving force - is the sign of a great soul; however,
as sexuality experience testifies, being owned by any other is also
an experience of terror. That is what the passage that Goethe transcribed
into his notebook highlights. One does not ordinarily think of the
philosophe Diderot as a proto-Romantic, but his writings on
art show him to be more inclined in this direction than we might want
to acknowledge. The following passage, which appears among his earlier
writings on art, the Salon of 1765, treats those Romantic themes
concerning inspiration and the difference between talent and genius.
Beware
of those whose pockets are full of esprit - of wit - and who
scatter this wit at every opportunity, everywhere. They have no demon
within them, they are not gloomy, or sombre, or melancholy, or silent.
They are are neither awkward or foolish. The lark, the chaffinch,
the linnet, the canary, they chirp and twitter all the livelong day,
at sunset they fold their head under their wing, and lo! They are
asleep. It is then that genius takes his lamp and lights it. And this
dark, solitary, savage bird, this untamable creature, with its gloomy
melancholy plumage, opens its throat and begins its song, makes the
groves resound and breaks the silence and darkness of the night.[v][5]
Here even the Encylopaediast Diderot testifies to
the solitary, melancholy, savage character of the creature who is
the instrument of nature; he acknowledges, too, the savage creator
dwells in night and darkness. But who could interpret this passage
as a literary construction without acknowledging these two features
of it: first, that Diderot uses the contrast between the day birds
and the solitary night bird to exemplify the difference between two
types of human beings, one sort the artificial person who seeks to
please, and because he or she fits in well with others, is content,
and the other sort, the violent, bold genius; and, second, that Diderot
uses this contrast between two types of persons to suggests the contrast
between the false self and the authentic self. In other words,
Diderot speaks of the division that cleaves both nature and the self
in two - with the more profound and more authentic being on the side
of darkness and death. The moi profond, astonishingly, is the
self that is operated by the other.[vi][6]
Throughout Romantic literature these dire
forces are depicted as directed towards death. Nature produces life,
but it also destroys it. Nature is directed as much towards death
as towards life. We cannot speak of a life force in nature, but only
of a force that strives towards both life and death, a lifedeath
force. The passion that drives that Werther in that Sturm und Drang
masterpiece, Die Leiden des junges Werthers, is a passion
for life and love the culminates in death. Werther's suicide is unavoidable:
Werther is driven by life - seized by a life force that is the essence
of nature - and this love, because its object is a married woman,
turns Werther against himself in a fashion that is unquestionably
enobling.
This Romantic view has persisted remarkably:
as evidence of its persistence, here is a passage from the 1960s French
Situationist Raoul Vaneigem, in which he rhapsodizes about death-haunted
life as the appropriation of the life by the baneful forces of our
reified projections of the re-externalized imagos (which he typically
calls "roles" or "stereotypes").
In
the totalizing perspective in which it conditions the whole of everyone's
life, and in which its real and its mythic power can no longer be
distinguished (both being both real and mythical), the process of
privative appropriation has made it impossible to express life any
way except negatively. Life in its entirety is suspended in a negativity
that corrodes it and formally defines it. To talk of life today is
like talking of rope in the house of a hanged man. Since the key of
will_to_live has been lost, we have been wandering in the corridors
of an endless mausoleum. The dialogue of chance and the throw of the
dice no longer suffices to justify our lassitude; those who still
accept living in well_furnished weariness picture themselves as leading
an indolent existence while failing to notice in each of their daily
gestures a living denial of their despair, a denial that should rather
make them despair only of the poverty of their imagination. Forgetting
life, one can identify with a range of images, from the brutish conqueror
and brutish slave at one pole to the saint and the pure hero at the
other. The air in this shithouse has been unbreathable for a long
time. The world and man as representation stink like carrion and there's
no longer any god around to turn the charnel houses into beds of lilies.
After all the ages men have died while accepting without notable change
the explanations of gods, of nature and of biological laws, it wouldn't
seem unreasonable to ask if we don't die because so much death enters
- and for very specific reasons - into every moment of our lives.[vii][7]
Our problematic is that of tracing the
filiation between the Romantic view of nature and the conception of
the spectacle that Raoul Vaneigem and his cohort, Guy Debord, sketched
and, more recently, Jean Baudrilland has developed.
Nature then is the concern. But "nature"
in what sense? The answer is more than obvious: nature as the realm
of competition between the an sich and the für sich.
The Romantic philosophers agreed that the division of being, and the
consequent competition between the an sich and the für sich,
is the source of all that is dire. That, after all, is the story that
Hegel recounts in the famous "Master and Slave" section of the Phenomenology
of Spirit.[viii][8]Notice
again the role that eristic model of the relation between different
aspects of reality plays in this passage.
All of the usual suspects as the source
of the baneful in nature depend upon this division. "What about sexuality
as the domain where dire forces prevail?" you might well ask. This
effort at rebuttal is without merit. For isn't it evident that sexuality
assigns us positions based on a polarity between male and female?
And, even more tellingly, that sexuality ensures that the position
of the other becomes a determinant of one's inmost strategies for
attaining satisfaction. Indeed the very relevance of the concept of
"strategy" to our achieving identity brings home the truth that this
relation between self and other really is a game in which one's interests
and desires possibly will be denied , and that for desire to be satisfied,
(even temporarily) it is necessary to subjected itself to the desire
of the other?
"And what about death as the home of
nature's baneful forces?," you ask. The response, as Schelling's philosophy
highlights, is obvious. The Romantics considered nature to be productivity
- to be active, to be the teeming fullness of life (the Fülle des
Lesbens alluded to above), for it is an inexhaustible multiplicity
and unremitting turbulence. It produces life, and in doing so produces
multiplicity, that is to say, division. So there we are: nature is
conflicted, divided. Moreover, for the Romantics, death, more than
being a boundary to life, is, in fact, its other. Death haunts nature
- inhabits it, even, - yet since nature, as Schelling pointed out,
is pure productivity, death can inhabit nature only by haunting it,
as a ghostly other. These are sentiments that the late (and somewhat
uncomprehending) Romantic Barrčs often referred to by the express
"la terre et les morts."That this feeling was widespread among
Romantics is clear from the Romantics' almost pathological interest
in ruins.
We begin our etiology of the dire by considering
the division of the Absolute into the an sich and the für
sich, for this division, I believe, is the sacrificial dynamic
at the origin of the baneful. The most renown text discussing this
division of the One is Hegel's Encyclopedia of Philosophical Science,
especially sections 244 to 248. In section 244, Hegel proposed, in
a passage that wants somewhat for clarity, that the Idea allows Nature
to go forth freely from itself. In section 247, he described Nature
as "the Idea in the form of Otherness." Yet he also characterized
the relationship between Nature and the Concept in a manner that hinted
at the potentially mischievous character of the duality, for he noted
that, while "Life is the Concept . . . come to its manifestation,"
life is difficult for the intellect to grasp, for intellect has an
affinity with "the abstract and the dead."
Kant had drawn a radical distinction between
two orders of thinking: one concerns phenomena (the contents of consciousness
itself), and that form of thinking, he stated, operates under the
regulation of the principles of Aristotelian logic. The other form
of thinking, which he termed "practical reason" concerns actions,
and operates on different protocols, protocols which he supposed were
capable of carrying us into the heart of the noumenal. Hegel tried
to overcome this duality at the heart of the Kantian system, by identifying
what the two forms of thinking have in common - a key principle of
Hegel's philosophy is that thought is realized first as activity,
for thinking first finds expression in outward form, in the actions
that human perform and the objects that they make. Thus, Hegel noted,
before thought turned self-reflexive and became thinking about thinking,
humans had already begun to think. However the form of their thought
was embedded in particulars, either in actual things they created
or in concrete thoughts (i.e., sensory images). Because the form of
our thinking is embedded in objects, we can as well discover a logical
structure in objects as we can in concepts themselves. Consequently,
thinking can discover itself in the mirror of its products.[ix][9] Nature
issues from the Idea and the Idea discovers itself in Nature. Each
is the Other for the other. The each is for the other is a fundamental
source of strife.
As the Absolute brings forth the Subject
and Nature, the two become each other's others, are intimately tied
to the other, insofar as the inner being of each is dependent on its
outward relation to the other. This first division establishes the
course through which the Absolute will attempt to take Nature back
into itself through discovering its rational being. Hegel generally
held a rather sanguine assessment of the role of division (it allows
for self-knowledge), but at times he allowed darker ideas to emerge.
As the Master-Slave passage in The Phenomenology of Spirit
makes evident, the dependence of the Master's inner being on his outward
relations makes him vulnerable on the other, and so exposes him to
death. Thus, in section 375, Hegel allowed that every individual animal
has "an original sickness" and "an innate germ of death."[x][10]
The vicissitudes of the being whose inner
character is decided by its relationships with others is the central
topic of German Romantic thought, the topic that became its principal
legacy. Consider how Kant transformed the British idea of the sublime.
Burke's commentary in his Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin
of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, rested on the distinction
between the experience of the beauty and that particular form of 'delight'
that he attributes to the experience of the sublime. While the source
of the former lies in the 'social passions' (predominantly sexual,
but including as well those concerned with friendship and sympathy
with others), the later originates with our instinctual drives for
self-preservation and turn mostly on pain and danger. To experience
the sublime requires that the object of experience be apprehended
as 'terrible' and therefore to be capable of instilling awe and fear.
It might seem odd to assert that something
that apprehended as 'terrible' can provoke 'delight,' but to those
who stricken by this apparent anomaly, Burke offered this rejoinder:
we experience such delight in situations that do not really threaten
our well-being, in which we are not truly exposed to dangers, and
we only have an idea of these. As Kant was to offer later, Burke proposed
that once we are ensconced in a safe haven, we can take pleasure in
nature's terrifying majesty. When we are at a safe remove from danger,
the idea of danger itself can set in play mental activities that invigorate
us.
That Kant drew much from Burke's Enquiry
is obvious. But it is a particular emphasis he gave to one aspect
of Burke's ideas on aesthetics that is especially important for our
purposes. The sublime, Kant stated, serves to remind us of something
about ourselves. A storm is a mere tumult in nature; what moves us
is that the storm serves us as a reminder of something in ourselves
- our status as moral (free) agents in the noumenal world. The grandeur
of nature arouses in us the idea of infinity; we try to think about
infinity, to formulate a precise concept of it, but we necessarily
fail. "Still," Kant wrote
the
mere ability to even think the given infinite without contradiction
is something that requires the presence in the human mind of a faculty
that is itself supersensible.. . . Therefore, the feeling of the sublime
in nature is respect for our own vocation which we attribute to an
Object of nature by a certain subreption (substitution of a respect
for the Object in place of one for the idea of humanity in our self
- the Subject); and this feeling renders, as it were, intuitable,
the supremacy of our cognitive faculties on the rational side over
the greatest faculty of sensibility.[xi][11]
The notion of subreption that Kant offered exerted
a decisive influence on the fate of German Romanticism[xii][12]. Subreption,
as Kant conceived it, involves a double moment: in the first, the
subject comes to understand the noblest aspects of itself through
apprehending an object; in the second, the object absorbs the subject
higher be-ing in consequence of the subject's projection - "substitution
of a respect for the Object in place of one for the idea of humanity
in our self." The double movement comprised in Kant's concept of subreption
established the fateful course of German Romanticism. The principle
at the heart of the idea, that we learn about that which in us is
highest - that which is most inward and closest to the moi profond
- through our relation to something beyond us, we shall see became
a cardinal element of German Romantic thought. In fact, the principle
established the destiny of thinking in the Nineteenth Century.
It also constituted a key item in the German
Romantic's legacy. The Romantic irony so crucial to the English Romantic
movement is a device for revealing that the opposition that confronts
the protagonist - or, since the protagonist is a stand-in for the
self, that confronts the self - arises from the self.[xiii][13] The
English Romantic lyric also demonstrates the subject and the object
share a single be-ing; yet it often depicts nature as self's adversary,
as a menacing realm that turns against the self and destroys it.[xiv][14]
An anxiety about division and duality also
pervades that heir to German Romanticism, German Expressionism. That
anxiety has its roots in the Romantic belief that beings that are
mutually dependent on one another cannot be fully real - that beings
must have an ontological basis in something higher if their be-ing
is to be ensured. That Kant's epistemology drew a sharp distinction
between the realms of noumena and phenomena is generally well known;
but there is another duality in Kant's system that is commonly recognized
today, although Romantic thinkers were very concerned with it. So
unfamiliar is this division that we must work at grasping it - and
the most effective way to do so is to consider how the philosophers
who succeeded Kant regarded his legacy.
That duality arises from the duality between
noumenon and phenomenon. Post-Kantian thinkers were critical of Kant's
extended commentary of the thing-in-itself, because it says so much
about something that exists outside any possible experience. The Romantics
honed this anomaly into an especially destructive attack on the Kantian
system; they pointed out that in order for Kant, or anyone, to say
anything about the thing-in-itself, then what he or she states must
be known by some Ego. And that implies that at some time some Ego
was conscious of a thing outside of consciousness. German Romantics
thinkers took that claim to be a simple contradiction.
Fichte formulated the problem thus: Was
the science of logic obliged to follow that same principles which,
it insisted, applied to all thinking whatsoever; or was it, alone
among all the sciences, able to ignore them? It seems patently obviously
that the former must be the case. Kant however, had argued that second
alternative was true. Kant believed that all people thought of what
is given in the deliberations of the special sciences (Kant's term
for these is "phenomena" ) by one set of rules (those of Aristotelian
logic), and of what is given in pure thought (i.e., noumenal) by another
(those rules that are formed in the spirit of transcendental dialectics).
So, according to Kant's philosophy, not
only is reality fissured but the "I" itself is split apart; every
thinking person is inhabited by two I's - one of which deliberates
on the world, the other of which deliberates on that which is given
in thinking. Kant's onetime follower, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, argued
this duality posed special difficulties. Fichte realized that Kant
thought of the "I," (i.e., the subject of thinking), as a thing-in-itself.
In Fichte's time it was thought that the rules of logic could be derived
from the determinations of the intellect (i.e., the faculty of reason).
Kant's treating the "I" as a thing-in-itself, however, made it impossible
to derive the system of logic from the systems of determinations of
the intellect because, according to the Kantian system, the "I" as
a thing-in-itself is unknowable. This left logic itself lacking any
ontological justification and therefore, though Kant would not have
admitted it, any ontological relevance. What is worse, it made it
impossible to suppose, as Kant had, that propositions of logic - which
are really propositions that arise from thinking about thinking -
also apply to thinking about things.
Fichte set about the task of remedying
these deficiencies in Kant's system by laying out principles that
were applicable to all thinking, whether thinking about the world
or thinking about thinking - principles that would remain applicable
whether thinking about colliding balls or thinking about concepts.
For the concept, Fichte announced can as well be the subject of scientific
or philosophical study as any other entity. That proposition would
have momentous effects in subsequent philosophy.
Fichte's goal for his science of science
(his Wissenshaftslehre) was to develop a science that would
be unitary. It would not begin with the opposition between the subjects
and objects (i.e., between concepts and objects). For if one starts
out with two separated parts that have no connection between one another,
one cannot subsequently put them back together in an integral system.[xv][15]
This is a topic we shall comment on in relation to Schelling, and
then again, in connection with that of Baudrillard. For now, it will
suffice to have pointed out that German Romanticism is the source
of eristic model out of which Baudrillard's idea of the precession
of simulacra arises. In fact the propositions that the sign has risen
to ascendency over the signifier is essentially an assertion that
the be-ing of beings has come to be identified with Be-ing itself
- an assertion that results from the forgetfulness of ontological
difference. So Fichte's system begins with the "I," the Ego, and attempts
to show that what we understand to be an object is the product of
an unconscious and unreflective activity of the Ego, which produces
the sensuously contemplated image in the imagination, while that which
we understand to be a concept is the product of conscious activities
of the ego. Reflective thought, therefore, is simply thought that
understands its active role in creating representations.[xvi][16]
Though Fichte began with the "I," he attempted
to preserve the mirror world of the not-I from unreality. His means
of doing so was essentially to fold the world that the 'I' knows back
into the circle of the self. The strategy is telling: Fichte's use
of the tactic of encompassing the domain of objective representation
within the more certain realm of the self gives evidence how troubling
nineteenth century German philosophers found the idea of a mirror
world of representation. So troubled was Fichte by the idea that he
ultimately failed to exorcise the spectre of the double from his philosophy,
and in the end he reproduced in his philosophy the dualism of the
Kantian system. Thus, in Fichte's system, one can discern the same
opposition that exists in Kant's between two halves of one and the
same Ego, one of which unconsciously produces the world of objective
representations in conformity with the laws of causality, space, and
time while the other consciously produces images of the world in conformity
with the requirements of morality. On Fichte's description, as on
Kant's, the Ego is split into separate parts that act in conformity
to separate principles; like Kant's, Fichte's philosophy suggested,
essentially, that there are two separate egos within each person.
And it could not explain, really, how the two parts are connected.
Fichte considered an object and its concept
as two different forms of existence of the same Ego - the two beings
were the result of the Ego's self-differentiation into a subjective
form and an objective form. Through the work of imagination, the Ego
created a product which it began to look upon as being separate from
itself. Furthermore, the Ego came to understand its activity of creating
a concept of an object as simply that of consciously re-producing
what had earlier been produced unconsciously. Indeed Fichte's philosophy
cast our consciousness of logical thinking as nothing more the schemas
of intuitive thinking come into awareness. In this way, the separation
of the Non-Ego from the Ego devalued the world of conception/representation,
turning it into a mere mirror world whose population is, in a certain
sense, supernumerary, redundant, excessive.[xvii][17] But
excess invites damnation. A pattern was established here: the division
of the Ego sets in a motion a process through which the Non-Ego turns
against the Ego; consequently, the Non-Ego is experienced as the habitation
of all that is dire
In fact, German Romantic philosophy suggest
this struggle between the different parts that come from the Absolute
assumes two forms. In one form, the divided parts of nature struggle
with one another. The self, or consciousness, is dependent on an object
(all consciousness is consciousness of something), while the object
of consciousness, to be recognized, is dependent on the consciousness.
Each is dependent on the other; but to be dependent on the other is
to be vulnerable to it, and vulnerability breeds strife. The second
form of the struggle is the struggle of what comes from the Absolute
against the Absolute itself; there is something offensive to infinite
Be-ing about its assuming the form of finitude - proponents of the
view asserted that the finitude, even of its products, is an insult
to the Infinite, that finitude wounds the Infinite. But the struggle
between the finite and the Infinite is not entirely one-sided: the
Infinite turns against the finite even as the finite rages against
the Infinite.
The latter form of the struggle of existence,
between what the Absolute produces and the Absolute itself, is evident
in Schopenhauer's gloomy views about the way the Will has with finite
beings and in Hegel's idea of the Cunning of Reason, the idea that
the Spirit deceives us, and cheats us and triumphs over all finite
beings in the end. But throughout German Romantic philosophy, we find
intimations of a dark force underlying particulars that frustrates
our efforts, that resists our efforts to come to terms with it. This
dark force, this dynamism, this forward-thrusting activity of relentless
self-creation will overwhelm all human efforts to contain it, to bridle
it, or to fathom it. Sometimes, as in Schopenhauer's writings and
Wagner's operas, the fear of source of this darkness rises almost
to the level of paranoia.
Schelling goes even farther than Fichte
or Hegel in his commentary on the precession of the inverted world
of representations. In his system, the realm of the for-itself becomes
a realm of dire forces that compel sacrifice. But Schelling did not
begin working out his system with this goal in mind; rather he started
by rejecting Fichte's symmetrical conception which cast Subject and
Nature as each other's other. That rejection was signal: had Schelling
worked out its consequences more fully (something he might have achieved
but for the pressures that certain theological conceptions exerted
on his philosophy), the evolution of Western thought would have followed
a different course. For the notion that there is a symmetry between
Be-ing and beings results in treating the transcendent pole of experience
as though it were like the entities that make up the immanent pole.[xviii][18] The
hypostatization of Be-ing results in the reduction of the status of
Be-ing to the be-ing of beings; another way of saying this - a way
of expressing the idea that adumbrates what Baudrillard has drawn
from German Romanticism - is to say that beings have absorbed Be-ing.
But Be-ing is the ground of the be-ing of beings, and reducing the
idea of Be-ing to the conceptual equivalent of the be-ing of beings
eventuates in the proposition that be-ing has lost its ontological
justification. It was onto this fateful course that the German Romantics
set Western thought.[xix][19]
Schelling's philosophy was partly an attempt
to remedy the deficiencies of the Fichtean system, even while preserving
Fichte's emphasis on activity. Like Fichte, he treated the opposition
between Subject and Object as an opposition within consciousness,
between the representations of a world (whether real or unreal) that
the mind produces freely and those images of the world that the mind
produces under constraints.[xx][20] Fichte
had relied on the notion of action to reconcile the divided parts
of the Ego. The manoeuver was not successful, however, for in the
end he described the two parts of the Ego as operating according to
different sets of protocols. What is worse, he proved unable to demonstrate
that the activities of the two halves of the Ego share a common origin
or energeia.
These difficulties forced Schelling to
reconsider the basis of Fichte's philosophy, Fichte's notions of Absolute
and of activity. Since Fichte had been unable to show that the subject
and the object share a common origin, the means Schelling proposed
to overcome the deficiencies of Fichte's system was to understand
more adequately the character of that originary Be-ing.[xxi][21]
He set out to show that both the subjective world and the objective
world emerged from a common origin, from an Absolute that was neither
subject nor object, but prior to both. Thus Schelling formulated his
philosophy of identity - a philosophy that proclaimed that the subject
and object originally existed together in a fused state of indistinguishability,
a fused "subject-object"; only in a secondary moment did the subject
and object emerge as distinct (even if dependent) entities from that
single fused Be-ing which he termed the Absolute.
The Absolute in the Schellingian system
is pure productivity, the urge for disclosure. It is, in another revelatory
convergence, very much what quantum theorists discuss as the quantum
vacuum. Fluctuations roil the quantum vacuum to create quantum particles;
quantum particles continually are being discharged from a void and
continually return to a void. The void in this conception is not exactly
nothing, though it does not contain entities - it is a state of minimum
energy in which quantum fluctuations lead to the temporary formation
of particle-antiparticle pairs in a manner that the uncertainty principle
of the German physicist Werner Heisenberg describes.[xxii][22] Because
the zero_point field is the lowest energy state, it is unobservable
(another feature of the quantum vacuum that resembles the Absolute
as Be-ing-in-itself). That it is everywhere, inside and outside of
us, that it permeates every atom in our bodies, makes us effectively
blind to it. We see only light the intensity of which is greater than
the energy of the zero_point field. Like Schelling's Absolute, it
a state pregnant with potentiality, even if it contains nothing actual,
a impetus to produce entities with opposite valencies. Physicists
see the beginning of the universe quantum vacuum possessing infinite
possibility, and out of these infinite possibility, the Universe was
realized, rather as in Schelling's system finitude issues from infinitude.
Schelling's description of this primal
productivity emphasized such terms as turbulence, conflict, and struggle.
It is a living force (and, we shall see, like all life, is directed
towards death). Human be-ing is simply the most self-conscious representative
of this primally unconscious drive; the role of artists, accordingly,
is to delve within themselves, into the dark forces that stir them,
and to bring the most violent internal struggles to recognition. Schelling
believed that there are violent clashes throughout nature: Volcanic
eruptions, metallic objects turning under the influence of magnetism,
electric sparks leaping from pole to pole are all evidence of the
drive of blind, mysterious forces to assert themselves. Every natural
phenomenon is the outcome of a struggle for self-assertion. So is
every piece of human behaviour - the only feature that distinguishes
human behaviour from other natural phenomenon is that in humans this
struggle can be raised to self-consciousness. This self-consciousness
finds its highest development in art, and the greatest works of art
are those that pulsate with the unconscious strivings of nature -
for that endows them with energy, power, vitality, force. The pulsations
which the work manifests are also pulsations of nature and their effect
on the viewer or listener is vitalizing.
The great artist is not fully conscious
of what he or she does. In fact, what distinguishes great art from
merely conventional art in Schelling's view (and it was a view that
was to exert great influence on Coleridge and through Coleridge on
the entire Romantic movement) is that the greater spirits of the stronger
artists are more in tune with, and open to being influenced by, forces
of which they are unconscious; poorer artists resist such impulses,
and instead produce work that is the result of scrupulous observation,
of carefully noting down what they saw in an accurate, lucid, almost
scientific manner.
But suppose that the universe is constantly
in movement, that there is never any stasis, suppose that the universe,
at heart, is activity, not a lump of inert matter, suppose it is infinite,
suppose it is constantly changing, never the same, not even at two
successive instants. How then could we describe the universe? Under
those conditions, any descriptive proposition we might offer would
represent a state of affairs that existed for one brief moment - it
would be like a snapshot (we could as well use the term "map") that,
so as soon as it is made, no longer represents any existing reality.
Our tendency, however is when thinking about reality is to think about
the snapshot (or map) and not the ever changing flowing, and in consequence,
out thinking misrepresents reality - it concerns nothing that has
any reality[xxiii][23].
A world-altering assertion the Romantics
promulgated was the assertion that reality is fundamentally without
structure, because it is basically something dynamic - it is a force,
a flow, a pressure, a field of action, a productivity. Anything that
has been brought into being (to say noting of what has been brought
into consciousness or put into language) is already on the way to
being dead, if not already dead. We cannot therefore know this underlying
dynamic reality through particulars, for they offer us only glimpses,
fragments of larger truth that is always in process, always evolving;
any attempt to grasp reality through this fragments produces a caricature
of reality, as absurb and grotesque a representation as trying to
capture the essence of the flowing stream in a single snapshot. No
account of this dynamism can be given, for it possess no stages -
no beginning, no middle, no end (inasmuch the very notion sof beginning,
middle and end are really products of that way of thinking that freezes
processes into a series of states). The universe is not a set of facts
with stable relations to one another, nor is it a pattern of events,
nor is it a collection of entities bound together by iron laws. It
is simply a perpetual activity of self-creation, perhaps more like
a flow than anything else. We cannot map this flow, for to make a
map is arrest - to destroy - what is the essence of reality.
According to this world-altering proposition, then, reality always
eludes us, always escapes us, always makes a mockery of our attempts
to grasp it.
But if the Absolute is, as Schelling claimed,
the urge for disclosure, then Be-ing, at the same time as it is Being-in-itself,
is always already Being-for-itself - Be-ing comes forth as Being-for-itself
in the same moment, and through the same process, as it emerges as
Being-in-itself.
for
being, actual real being, is precisely self-disclosure. If it is to
be as One then it must reveal itself in itself; but it does not reveal
itself if it is just itself, if it is not an other in itself, and
is in this other the One for itself.[xxiv][24]
That is, the Absolute is always already a divided
being ("it does not reveal itself if it is just itself, if it is not
another in itself."). The infinite Absolute must show itself within
the realm of finitude, for it would not be spirit if it did not reveal
itself. Spirit, Schelling wrote
is
only through itself, through its own action.
Now,
that which is (originally) object is as such necessarily also finite.
Because spirit is not originally object, it cannot be originally finite,
not according to its own nature. - Infinite then? But it is spirit
only insofar as it is object itself, that is, insofar as it becomes
finite. Thus, it is not infinite without becoming finite, nor
can it become finite (for itself) without becoming infinite[xxv][25].
Even self-consciousness involves limitation, and
hence division[xxvi][26]
But polarity tends towards opposition, and opposition tends towards
strife, and strife tends towards death, and death vaporizes all that
is real. This is a story we shall trace in Baudrillard..
Only
that of me which is limited, so to speak, comes into consciousness;
the limiting activity falls outside of all consciousness, precisely
because it is the cause of all limitedness. The limitedness must appear
to be independent of me because I can only see only my limitedness,
and not the activity through which it is posited.[xxvii][27]
Schelling endeavoured to explain through
analogy how the Absolute, even while it is divided, remains nevertheless
One.
As
the eye, when it sees itself in the reflection, e.g., in the mirror,
posits itself, intuits itself, only to the extent that it posits what
reflects - the mirror - as nothing for itself, and as it is, so to
speak, One act of the eye, by which it posits itself, sees itself,
and does not see what reflects, does not posit it; in this way does
totality posit or intuit itself, by not-positing, not-intuiting the
particular; both are One act in the totality.[xxviii][28]
Elsewhere the conflict revealed in the stressed
syntax of this passage splits the tenuously reconciled object and
its double apart, and Schelling then expounded a darker view of nature.
In Philosophie und Religion (1804) the balefulness of nature
has its origin in a prior moment, an earlier breaking with the ground
of being.
there
is no constant transition from the Absolute to the real, the origin
of the world of the senses can only be thought as a complete breaking
off from absoluteness, by a leap. If philosophy is to deduce the origin
of real things in a positive manner from the Absolute, then there
would have to be a positive ground in the Absolute.. . . Philosophy
has only a negative relation to things that appear, it rather proves
that they are not rather than that they are. . . . The Absolute is
all that is real: finite things, on the other hand, are not real;
their ground cannot lie in a communication of reality to them or to
their substrate, which would have emanated from the Absolute, it can
only lie in a move away, in a fall (Abfall)
from the Absolute.[xxix][29]
Here Schelling described the finite's coming forth
from the Absolute as an Abfall (a fall) - in Philosophie
und Religion he went even farther, and referred to the descent
of the finite things from the Absolute the "Urzufall" ("primal
accident").
That claim carries us to the very core
of the Romantic's sense of nature as baneful character. The idea that
the "origin of the world of the senses" represents "a complete breaking
off from absoluteness, by a leap" carries with it the conviction that
whatever inhabits the realm of finitude is marked for destruction,
since it possesses no ontological warrant. The thinking that produced
this view is clear: the Absolute cannot be responsible for this limitation,
for it cannot be the Absolute that pronounces the sentence of death
on all that comes forth into finitude. Therefore the destructive element
must belong to matter.
Schelling reiterated his convictions about
disconnection of beings from Be-ing in his1809 text, On the Essence
of Human Freedom:
the
origin of no finite thing leads immediately back to the infinite,
it can instead only be grasped via the sequence of causes and effects,
which is, though itself endless, whose law has, therefore, no positive
but a merely negative meaning, that namely, nothing finite can arise
immediately out of the Absolute and be deduced from it. Whence already
in this law the ground of the being of finite things is expressed
as an absolute breaking off from the infinite.[xxx][30]But try
as he might to deny that matter was an inertial principle, and that
material things had broken off from the Absolute, he was not able
to sustain these claims.
The
ground of the be-ing of finite things expresses itself as an absolute
rupture with the Infinite. Division is privative - its effect is to
render what it divides unreal. For what belongs to the realm of finitude
exists in space, and space is a grid that separates point from point,
and its measure is the very index of separation and division. Because
space itself is a matrix of individuated positions, it renders all
spatial being unreal.
As
opposed to life in the totality, particular life can only appear as
an endless disintegration into difference - without identity - as
endless non-identity, pure extension. For the inner identity is negated
by the relation of the positions to each other. But this is the affirmative
[i.e., the link that transmits be-ing]. Accordingly, the particular
life of things, as opposed to life in the infinite substance, i.e.,
the being-affirmed of things separated from infinite affirmation,
from identity, can only appear as endless difference, as completely
privation of identity, accordingly as a powerless disintegration,
as pure extension.[xxxi][31]
As dire as division is, however, consciousness requires
it. For consciousness is consciousness of something viz., and
the objects of consciousness we call "phenomena," that is, "that which
appears." If there are appearances, there must be that which appears,
and in addition there must that to which it appears. So consciousness
demands division, and that implies that the absolutely identical already
separates itself in the first act of consciousness. Schelling explains
this by referring to the freedom that consciousness requires - the
conscious subject separates itself from the Absolute, and, even, from
the all other finite objects, by its freedom.[xxxii][32]
By
positing myself as myself I oppose myself to everything else,
consequently to the entire universe. Egoity (Ichheit)
is therefore the universal expression of isolation, of separation
from the totality (All), and as noting can be separated from
totality, given its infinity, except by its being finitely posited,
i.e., with negation, then egoity is the general expression and highest
principle of all finitude, i.e., of everything which is not
absolute totality, absolute reality. How the infinite, in which
there is no negation, could possibly be the cause of privations, of
limitations is absolutely incomprehensible.[xxxiii][33]
We might well share Schelling's puzzlement.
The effort to free ourselves from this puzzlement could begin with
asking ourselves, "Whence arises this idea that the world of the senses
arises from a breaking-off from the Absolute, by a leap?" "Or for
that matter, whence arises this notion of the illusory character of
the realm of particulars." We know that the transition from infinitude
to finitude does not by itself entail the separation of beings from
Be-ing. The doctrine that objects issue out of Infinite Be-ing as
an act of love, and that Infinite Be-ing bestows infinite worth on
all that is and holds them all within its embrace, is one that religious
thinkers have propounded time and again: it grounded a very different
metaphysics of nature than that of Schelling or the other Jena Romantics.
The coherence of the older metaphysic establishes.that is not with
the help of logic that we will discern the motivation for Schelling's
ideas about the transition from infinitude to finitude.[xxxiv][34]
As we shall see, we have turn to theological ideas to explain the
conclusion. Schelling's thought was deeply influenced by emanationism,
and it was likely emantionist/gnostic convictions about the inertness/negativity
of matter that led Schelling to attribute a low-grade reality to matter.[xxxv][35]
The pressures that Schelling's heterodox
beliefs exerted on his system resulted in his formulating an unusual
conception of spirit in nature. Like the Ego, the general "I,"
in Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre, the Absolute in Schelling's
philosophy is "the basic force" to which the universe owes its original
cause; however, unlike Fichte's Ego, Schelling's Absolute lacks consciousness.
In sum, the Absolute in Schelling's system is much like Fichte's absolute
'I,' projected into nature and robbed of its consciousness.[xxxvi][36] What
it is, is activity -- it is dynamism, pure and simple. It is the Creator,
made immanent, and assuming some of the attributes of the be-ing of
beings. But we must examine other implications of the division of
nature before we are in a position to consider those theological determinants.
Schelling's belief that reality is bifurcated
was associated with the idea that consciousness itself is divided.
His division of reality into the realms of the infinitude and the
finite is paralleled by a division in subject and object.
There
is no consciousness without something which is both excluded and attracted.
That which is conscious of itself excludes what it is conscious of
as not itself, and yet must also attract it as, precisely, that of
which it is conscious, thus as itself, only in another form.[xxxvii][37]
Self and Non-Self are locked togethr in
a circle that inevitably will spawn conflict. For the be_ing of the
subject is dependent on the be_ing of the object (there is no awareness
that is not an awareness of something) and the be_ing of the object
is dependent on the be_ing of subject (they are phenomena for a subject).
The inner be_ing of each is dependent on its external relations; this
relationship of mutual dependency that leads them to turn both against
one another and against the source of their be-ing. Such was the ontology
of the Jena Romantics. Thus, a view of nature as a realm of division,
in which the encounter of each element with every other is of the
nature of limitation and opposition (and is experienced by consciousness
as restriction and strife), appears in Friedrich Schiller's Letters
on the Aesthetic Education of Man. There Schiller, taking a Kantian
turn, argues that it is the sundered condition in which humans live
that makes art necessary:
If
in the dynamic State of rights it is as force that one man encounters
another, and imposes limits upon his activities; if in the ethical
State of duties Man sets himself over against man with all the majesty
of the law, and puts a curb upon his desires: in those circles where
conduct is governed by beauty, in the aesthetic State, none may appear
to the other except as form, or confront him except as an object of
free play. To bestow freedom by means of freedom is the fundamental
law of this kingdom.
The
dynamic State can merely make society possible, by letting one nature
be curbed by another; the ethical State can merely make it (morally)
necessary, by subjecting the individual will to the general; the aesthetic
State alone can make it real, because it consummates the will of the
whole through the nature of the individual . . . Taste alone brings
harmony into society, because it fosters harmony into society, because
it fosters harmony in the individual. All other forms of perception
divide man, because they are founded exclusively either upon the sensuous
or upon the spiritual part of his being; only the aesthetic mode of
perception makes of him a whole, because both his natures must be
in harmony if he is to achieve it. All other forms of communication
divide society, because they relate exclusively either to the private
receptivity or to the private proficiency of its individual members,
hence to that which distinguishes man from man; only the aesthetic
mode of communication unites society, because it relates to that which
is common to all. The pleasures of the senses we enjoy merely as individuals,
without the genus which is immanent within us having any share of
them at all; hence we cannot make the pleasures of the senses universal,
because we are unable to universalize our own individuality. The pleasures
of knowledge we enjoy merely as genus, and by carefully removing from
our judgement all trace of individuality; hence we cannot make the
pleasures of reason universal, because we cannot eliminate traces
of individuality from the judgements of others as we can from our
own. Beauty alone do we enjoy at once as individual and genus, i.e.,
as representatives of the human genus.[xxxviii][38]
Beauty alone overcomes division without thwarting
individuality.
Schiller proclaimed the re-integrative
powers of art. So did Schopenhauer, but with this difference: for
Schopenhauer aesthetic experience offered only temporary respite from
the brutal way that the Will has with us. For the most part, we know
only the realm of division, plurality - we know the realm through
which the Will works, but do not know the inward workings of the Will
itself. Schopenhauer extended Kant's distinction between the phenomenal
and noumenal realms by connecting the Kantian notion of the phenomenal
world, the realm of appearance, with the Vendantic notion of maya,
the realm of illusion. Many other thinkers made that same connection,
not in the least because of Schopenhauer's formidable reputation,
and increasingly saw the world dissolve into phantasms.
Schopenhauer named the agent of this erosion
- it was division, specifically the division between the subject and
the object.
Therefore
the world as representation, in which aspect alone we are here considering
it, has two essential, necessary, and inseparable halves. The one
half is the object, whose forms are space and time, and through
these plurality. [Note that Schopenhauer that the forms of space and
time are matrices of division.] But the other half, the subject,
does not lie in space and time, for it is whole and undivided in every
representing being. Hence a single one of these beings with the object
completes the world as representation just as fully as do the millions
that exist. And if that single one were to disappear, then the world
of representation would cease to exist. [What a remarkable assertion
of the radical contingency of beings!] Therefore these halves are
inseparable even in thought, for each of the two has meaning and existence
only through the other; each exists with the other and vanishes. [We
remarked that Hegel and Schelling both held a similar notion, that
the inner being of each term in a relation depends on its external
relation, and that dependency leaves being vulnerable. The division
between the subject and the object makes each dependent on the other
- this mutuality is the reason for the contingency of the being of
each term in the relation.] They limit each other immediately; where
the object begins, the subject ceases. [Here Schopenhauer reiterates
that Spinozistic theme of German Romanticism, that every determination
is a negation.] The common or reciprocal nature of this limitation
is seen in the very fact that the essential, and hence universal,
forms of every object, namely space, time and causality, can be found
and fully known, starting from the subject, even without the knowledge
of the object itself, that is to day, in Kant's language, they reside
a priori in our consciousness. [xxxix][39]
For Schopenhauer finite objects they are merely
the reflections of a mirror world, ghostly doubles to the operations
of Will, and no more than phantasmal.Schopenhauer elaborates his thesis
on the unreality of finite particulars in Parerga and Paralimpomena,
a collection of "aphorisms written from a popular viewpoint." There
he repeats again the idea that material reality is nothing more than
phantasmagoria.
In the end, however, Schopenhauer rejected
that thesis, arguing that the belief that there is no ultimate reality
derives from the failure to fathom the inner essence of things. In
the course of his critique of the thesis of universal unreality, he
provided a telling analysis of the dynamic that generates that mistaken
thesis (an analysis that is germane to more recent commentaries on
"the spectacle," "simulation" and "simulacra").
The
fundamental character of all things is their fleeting nature and transitoriness.
In nature we see everything, from metal to organism corroded and consumed
partly by its own existence, partly through conflict with something
else.. . .
We
complain of the obscurity in which we pass our lives without understanding
the connection of existence as a whole, but in particular that between
ourselves and the whole. . . . it really looks as if a demon had mischievously
obstructed from us all further knowledge in order to gloat over our
embarrassment.
But
this complaint is not really justified, for it springs from an illusion,
the result of the false fundamental view that the totality of things
came from an intellect and consequently existed as mere mental
picture or representation before it became actual [consider the
etiology of this conception, in Plato's philosophy, to discern what
set us on the path to the theory of simulation] and that accordingly
as it had sprung from knowledge, it was bound to be wholly accessible
thereto and thus capable of being fathomed and exhaustively treated.
[We might here comment, were there space enough, on the arrogance
that impels reason to deny the mystery of Be-ing.] But in truth the
case might rather be that all we complain of not knowing is not known
by anyone, indeed is in itself not even knowable at all, in other
words, is not capable of being represented in anyone's head. For the
representation, in whose domain all knowing is to be found
and to which all knowledge therefore refers, is only the external
side of existence, something secondary and additional, hence something
that was not necessary for the maintenance of things generally and
thus of the world as a whole, but merely for the maintenance of individual
animal beings. [What phantasms there are in animal brains are fitted
only to ensure the animal survives, and do not accurately picture
reality as such.] Therefore the existence of things in general and
as a whole enters knowledge only per accidens and consequently
to a very limited extent. It forms only the background of the picture
in animal consciousness where objects of the will are the essential
thing and occupy first place. Now it is true that, by means of this
accident, the entire world arises in space and time, that is, the
world as representation which has no existence at all outside of knowledge.
On the other hand, the innermost essence of this world, that which
exists in itself, is quite independent of such and existence. [xl][40]
Schopenhauer, then, discerned that what we have
taken to be our idea of the real is "only the external side of existence,
something secondary and additional." These ideas about the real do
not represent reality as it is - they serve only the interest of survival.
Schopenhauer, though he considered it to be mistaken, recognized that
the belief that these representations (the für sich to the
Will's an sich) are all that there is - and that they are as
nothing - menaced post-Kantian philosophy.
Schopenhauer may not have embraced the
idea there nothing underlies phenomenal appearances, but he did acknowledge
its presence. Indeed, even Schopenhauer's bęte noir, Hegel,
recognized the uncanny stranger that stood at the threshold, about
to ente.
.
. . people claimed to have discovered and proved there is no
knowledge of truth. It was said the God, the essence of the world
and of the spirit, is incomprehensible and unintelligible; that the
spirit had to stand by religion, and religion itself by believing,
feeling, and intimations, without any knowledge based on reason. It
was said that knowledge was concerned not with the nature of the absolute,
of God, and of what is true and absolute in nature and in spirit,
but rather partly with either the negative principle that nothing
true is known (only what is untrue, temporal, and ephemeral enjoys
the privilege of being known); or - and this actually should be subsumed
under the negative - that knowledge is concerned with externalities,
i.e., merely historical and contingent circumstances under which the
ostensible knowledge itself belonged. Such knowledge was to be taken
merely as an historical fact and investigated critically and learnedly
from all those external perspectives - its content could yield nothing
serious. These people went as far as Pilate, the Roman proconsul.
When Pilate heard Christ use the word "truth," he replied with the
question "What is truth?" like one who was through with the word and
knew that there was no knowledge of truth. Thus what always had been
considered the most disgraceful and unworthy thing, to renounce knowledge
of truth, was exalted by our age as the highest triumph of the spirit..
. .
Not
to know what is true but to recognize only temporal and contingent
appearances - only vanities - it was this conceit which spread in
philosophy and is still spreading in our time and loudly proclaiming
itself.[xli][41]
In the end, as everyone knows, Schopenhauer and
Hegel, turned the uncanny stranger away; but the stranger persisted,
and a short time later, Friedrich Nietzsche would usher him in.
Part III: Implosion
Soon signs started appearing. THE MOST PHOTOGRAPHED
BARN IN AMERICA. We counted five signs before we reached the site.
There were forty cars and a tour bus in the makeshift lot. . ..Murray
maintained a prolonged silence, occasionally scrawling some notes
in a little book. 'No one sees the barn,' he said finally. A long
silence followed. "Once you've seen the signs about the barn, it becomes
impossible to see the barn. . . . We've agreed to be part of a collective
perception. This literally colors our vision. A religious experience
in a way, like all tourism."
__Don DeLillo, White Noise. (New York:
Viking Penguin, 1985): p 12.
The judgement of the universal unreality
of things is pronounced first by Friedrich Nietzsche, who arrived
at this idea as consequence of the death of God, i.e., of the truth
of being.
Men
of philosophical disposition are known for their constant premonition
that our everyday reality, too, is an illusion, hiding another, totally
different kind of reality. It was Schopenhauer who considered the
ability to view at certain times all men and things as mere phantoms
or dream images to be the true mark of philosophic talent. The person
who is responsive to the stimuli of art behaves toward the reality
of dream much the way the philosopher behaves toward the reality of
existence: he observes exactly and enjoys his observations, for it
is by these images that he interprets life, by these processes that
he rehearses it. Nor is it by pleasant images only that such plausible
connections are made: the whole divine comedy of life, including its
somber aspects, its sudden balkings, impish accidents, anxious expectations,
moves past him, not quite like a shadow play - for it is he himself,
after all, who lives and suffers through these scenes - yet never
without giving a fleeting sense of illusion; and I imagine that many
persons have reassured themselves amidst the perils of dream by calling
out "It is a dream! I want it to go on." I have even heard of people
spinning out the causality of one and the same dream over three or
more successive nights. All these facts clearly bear witness that
our innermost being, the common substratum of humanity, experiences
dreams with deep delight and a sense of real necessity.[xlii][42]
Walter Benjamin exfoliated the epistemological implications
of this implosion his great, uncompleted text that he took to calling
the "Arcades Project."
On
the doctrine of the ideological superstructure. It seems, at first
sight, that Marx wanted to establish here only a causal relation between
the superstructure and infrastructure. But already the observation
that ideologies of the superstructure reflect conditions falsely and
invidiously go beyond this. The question, in effect, is the following:
if the infrastructure in a certain way (in the materials of thought
and experience) determines the superstructure, but if the determination
is not reducible to simple determination, how is it then - entirely
apart from any question about the originating cause - to be characterized?
As its expression. The superstructure is the expression of the infrastructure.
The economic conditions under which society exists are expressed in
the superstructure - precisely as, with the sleeper, an overfull stomach
finds not its reflection but its expression in the content of dreams,
which, from a casual point of view, it may be said to "condition."
The collective, from the first, expresses the condition of its life.
These find their expression in the dream and their interpretation
in the awakening.[xliii][43]
What the passage fails to acknowledge are the new
ontological theories that were the companion pieces of this epistemology
that casts knowledge as fantastical.
Benjamin's ontology has its roots in the
ontology of the German Romantics. For, Benjamin, as for the Schelling
and Hegel, Being is divided, between Being-for-itself and Being-in-itself.
For Benjamin, as for Fichte, Schelling, Hegel and Schopenhauer, Being-for-itself
represents the double world that reflects Be-ing back to itself -
though in a reflection that does not depict it as it is in itself,
but transforms. One might say these reflections are maps that represent
the terrain they refer to only imperfectly, except that these maps
are the only means through the terrain can be cognized. But Benjamin
also extended the Romantics' description of Being-for-itself by formulating
a rather Schopenhauerian analysis of the illusory character of the
object world. Though he did not adopt exactly a Schopenhauerian position
on the evolutionary function of these illusory appearances, he did
argue, as Schopenhauer had, that the object world has only a delirious
relation to the subject - the same relation that the dream has to
the "overfull stomach." And Benjamin goes even farther than Schopenhauer
in stating that Vorstellungen are merely mental effects of
causes whose character is hardly registers in the content of the mental
representation; thus, analyzing the passage just cited from a literary
point of view, one is struck by the suggestion of the realm of objective
representations is, strictly, excessive, and unnecessary.
Benjamin's belief that objective appearances
are, strictly, de trop has a striking parallel in Schelling's
system.
It
was surely a meaningful dream that dead matter be the sleep of the
forces of representation, that animal life be a dream of the monads,
that the life of reason finally be a state of universal vigilance.
For what is matter than extinguished spirit? In matter, all duplicity
is canceled, its state is a state of absolute identity and calm.
We might recall that Freud described all life as
tending toward that inertia - that the goal of all be-ing is unicity
of death. That parallel tells us much about how German thought of
the nineteenth (and early twentieth century) was in thrall to the
idea of a doubled world of consciousness, of representations, of Spirit.
Accord that world primacy, in the fashion of the Gnostics, and one
has Baudrillard's ontology.
But that is getting ahead of story. Schelling
continued the passage we have just cited:
In
the transition from homogeneity to duplicity, one world slips into
twilight; with the restitution of duplicity, the world itself arises.[xliv][44]
One might conjecture that if the world of objective
representations is de trop, its bonds to the absolute would
be tenuous. Benjamin drew exactly that conclusion. But however tenuous
objective representations may be, and however phantasmal by consequence,
Benjamin nonetheless acknowledged what Schelling and Hegel had, that
the division between of Be-ing and beings turns the one against the
other - and in this struggle, as in all struggles, the identity of
the victory is never certain. The belief that there is a eristic relationship
between beings and Be-ing, that objective representations (Vorstellungen)
have turned against Be-ing, a belief Benjamin drew from the German
Romantics, is a part of legacy that Benjamin bequeathed to Raoul Vaneigem,
Guy Debord, and, Jean Baudrillard, each of whom develop that heritage
in a characteristic fashion.
Benjamin proclaimed film to the paradigmatic
medium of the world of objective representations. But if the division
between Be-ing and beings has turned the realm of Vorstellungen
against Be-ing, than that oppositional dynamic must be evident in
film, the paradigmatic medium of objective representation. Benjamin
reasoned exactly so. He stated
One
can characterize the problem of the form of the new art straight on:
When and how will the worlds of form which, without our assistance,
have arisen, for example, in mechanics, in film, in the new physics,
and which have subjugated us, makes it clear for us what manner of
nature they contain? When will we reach a state of society in which
these forms, or those arising from them, reveal themselves to us a
natural forms? Of course, this brings to light only one moment in
the dialectical essence of technology. (Which moment, is hard
to say: antithesis if not synthesis.) In any case, there lives in
technology another impulse as well: to bring about objectives strange
to nature, along with means that are alien and inimical to nature
- measures that emancipate themselves from nature and master it.[xlv][45] [The
Arcades Project, K3a,2]
The remark, of course, reflects the views of his
colleague, Max Horkheimer, on technology; it is also reminiscent of
George Lukács ideas about reification.[xlvi][46] It
was, one must assume, an element of the Zeitgeist. This fragment of
the Zeitgeist proved to be an augur of the future, for, in coupling
the idea that consciousness (ideology) is a dream released from the
belly of reality with the notion that to which nature has given rise
will "emancipate themselves from nature and master it", Benjamin lays
the groundwork for the thought of Raoul Vaneigem and Guy Debord.
Another association went into the making
of the legacy that Benjamin bequeathed to Baudrillard. Benjamin's
idea that consciousness (ideology) is a dream released from the belly
of reality led him into seeing all artifacts, all built reality, all
human transformations of nature, as projections of dreams.[xlvii][47] Fashion,
advertising, building and politics are all outcomes of dream vision.
[The Arcades Project, K1, 4] The historian, Benjamin proposed,
must become practiced in the analysis of dreams.
Another idea that formed part of Benjamin's
legacy to social theory of erosion was that of the dialectical image.
Benjamin's expositions of his conception of the dialectical image
closely parallel Lukács' ideas on reification. How closely can be
discerned from the following passage:
Corresponding
to the form of the new means of production, which in the beginning
is still ruled by the form of the old (Marx), are images in the collective
consciousness in which the old and the new interpenetrate. These images
are wish images; in them the collective seeks both to overcome and
to transfigure the immaturity of the social product and the inadequacies
in the social organization of production. At the same time, what emerges
in these wish images is the resolute effort to distance oneself from
all that is antiquated - which includes, however, the recent past.
These tendencies deflect the imagination (which is given impetus by
the new) back upon the primal past. In the dream in which each epoch
entertains images of its successor, the later appears wedded to elements
of primal history - that is, to elements of a classless society. And
the experiences of such a society - as stored in the unconscious of
the collective - engender, through interpenetration with what is new,
the utopia that has left its trace in a thousand configurations of
life, from enduring edifices to passing fashions.[xlviii][48]
The reified relations between commodities in Lukács,
the delusory world of the chthonic in Benjamin - both are ghostly
doublings of the actual world of objects that end by attacking what
they were first set over against. More striking is that in both Benjamin's
and Lukács' writing we can discern a similar eristic model to that
which Fichte, Schelling and Hegel's philosophy presuppose, on which
the relation of separate dimensions of reality must be one of strife.
What is different in Benjamin, of course,
in the emphasis of the delirious character of the reified representation
of social relations. Contemporary reality, Benjamin argued, has a
paradoxical constitution - contemporary be-ing combines, intimacy
and distance, proximity and distance, in a fused attribute. That strange,
and ontologically destabilizing, notion of the essential togetherness
of proximity in contemporary reality has more far reaching implications.
Benjamin was required to accord that sort of reality value to his
dialectical images, to be sure, for in order to combine past and future,
then they can't have the reality value of something that exists as
a singular being with definite and unique spatial-temporal co-ordinates.
That is, the same pressure that led quantum physicists to ontological
quandaries over the quark that finally brought physicists to argue
that quantum entities cannot be objects in the sense that we commonly
mean by "object" required Benjamin to adopt the position that the
mirror world of production must have something of an ideal character
- that is to say, they must be in some degree unreal, even though,
to add paradox to paradox, they exert effects on material reality,
producing everything from enduring edifices to passing fashion trends.[xlix][49]
But the issue is more general: It is not
only the dialectic between the past and the present, or between the
near and the far that wreaks havoc for the materialist ontology -
it is more generally the dialectic itself - the dialectic set in motion
by the division of Being. For the dialectic assigns to objects paradoxical
qualities, and the logic of material reality proscribes an object
from possessing simultaneously, incompatible properties. Thus Benjamin:
It
is the unique provision of Baudelaire's poetry that the image of the
woman and the image of death intermingle in a third: that of Paris.
The Paris of poems is a sunken city, and more submarine than subterranean.
The chthonic elements of the city - its topological formations, the
old abandoned bed of the Seine - have evidently found in him a mold.
Decisive for Baudelaire in the "death-fraught idyll" of the city,
however, is a social, a modern substrate. The modern is a principal
accent of his poetry. As spleen, it fractures the ideal ("Spleen
et idéal"). But precisely the modern, modernité, is always
citing primal history. Here, this occurs through the ambiguity peculiar
to the social relations and products of this epoch. Ambiguity is the
manifest imaging of the dialectic, the law of dialects at a standstill.
The standstill is utopia and the dialectical image, therefore a dream
image. Such an image is afforded by the commodity per se: as fetish.
Such an image is presented by the arcades, which are house no less
than street. Such an image is the prostitute - seller and sold in
one.[l][50]
Opposition - between self and other (nature), between
male and female, between past and present, between life and death
- the dialectical terms of Hegel's philosophy: these, for Benjamin,
give evidence of ideality. After all, had not that been the conclusion
of those who had thought most deeply the coincidental oppositorum?
Since objective beings give evidence that they harbour such oppositions
- such duality - does not that entail that they are, at least
in some measure, unreal.[li][51]
Thus we discover whence exactly the idea
that reality has dissolved into the phantasmagoria of the dream world
has arisen. It has arisen from the curious conclusion regarding the
status that must be accorded to what is Other for Being-in-itself
- the inference that what is Other than Being-in-itself must Other-than-Be-ing.[lii][52] This
was the belief that lead thinkers to see reality dissolving into phantasms.
Benjamin's identification of what is Other
for Be-ing with what is Other-than-be-ing was a fateful legacy. The
late Situationist Raoul Vaneigem , in his book The Revolution of
Everyday Life, makes explicit that the division of being is the
condition that is responsible for the sense that reality has vaporized
into the unreality of the spectacle.
Our
efforts, our boredom, our defeats, the absurdity of our actions -
all stem most of the time from the imperious necessity in our present
situation of playing hybrid parts, parts which appear to answer our
desires, but which are really antagonistic to them. "We would live,"
says Pascal, "according to the ideas of others; we would live an imaginary
life, and to this end we cultivate appearances. Yet in striving to
beautify and preserve this imaginary being we neglect everything authentic."
This was an original thought in the seventeenth century; at a time
when the system of appearances was still hale, its coming crisis was
apprehended only in the inhibitive flashes of the most lucid. Today,
amidst the decomposition of all values, Pascal's observation states
only what is obvious to everyone. By what magic do we attribute the
liveliness of human passions to lifeless forms? Why do we succumb
to the seduction of borrowed attitudes? What are roles?[liii][53]
Projected desires are reified, and in the end come
to control us. Their effectivity is real, but their status as projections
ensures that they present themselves as having a phantasmal character.
The structure of the process Vaneigem described is similar to that
which Herder, Schelling and Hegel all discussed: it began with consigning
objects to a lowly status and ended with depicting the discredited
realm as one of dire forces that extract the tribute of sacrifice.
What pressures impelled the progression
from the view that the realm of objects has a low-grade status to
the view that it harbours dire forces? Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling's
deliberations on Be-ing produced a fateful conclusion: whatever Be-ing
engenders is inevitably dual: "In short: Every organization is
an organization only insofar as it is turned simultaneously towards
two worlds. Every organization is a Dyas."[liv][54]
The notion of self-identity is key to concept of objecthood, and the
Romantics put that the singularity - the self-identity - of objects
into question. Because the concept of self-identity is crucial to
the notion that the be-ing of beings has an ultimate ontological justification,
so the rejection of the concept of identity leads to convictions of
the unreality of natural objects. Thus, in the introduction to the
System of Transcendental Philosophy, Schelling asserted
If
all knowing has, as it were, two poles, which mutually presuppose
and demand one another, they must seek each other in all the sciences;
. . .
That is, proposes that the division in Be-ing leaves
the divided parts in an unstable relationship. The inner being of
each depends upon its relations to something other than itself. This
leaves each part vulnerable, for the other can, and does, decide its
fate. An eristic relation between the two parts inevitably results.
Schelling continued:
hence
there must necessarily be two basic sciences, and it must be
impossible to set out from the one pole without being driven toward
the other. The necessary tendency of all natural science is
thus to move from nature to intelligence. This and nothing else is
at the bottom of the urge to bring theory into the phenomena
of nature.- The highest consummation of natural science would be the
complete spiritualising of all natural laws into laws of intuition
and thought. The phenomena (the matter) must wholly disappear, and
only the laws (the form) remain. Hence it is, that the more lawfulness
emerges in nature itself, the more the husk disappears, the phenomena
themselves become more mental, and at length vanish entirely. The
phenomena of optics are nothing but a geometry whose lines are drawn
by light, and this light itself is already of doubtful materiality.
In the phenomena of magnetism all material traces are already disappearing,
and in those of gravitation, which even scientists have thought it
possible to conceive of merely as an immediate spiritual influence,
nothing remains but its law, whose large scale execution is the mechanism
of the heavenly motions. - The completed theory of nature would be
that whereby the whole of nature was resolved into an intelligence.
- The dead and unconscious products of nature are merely abortive
attempts that she makes to reflect herself; inanimate nature so-called
is actually as such an immature intelligence, so that in her phenomena
the still unwitting character of intelligence is already peeping through.
- Nature's highest goal, to become wholly an object to herself, is
achieved only through the last and highest order of reflection, which
is none other than man; or, more generally, it is what we call reason,
whereby nature first completely returns into herself, and by which
it becomes apparent that nature is identical from the first with what
we recognize in ourselves as the intelligent and the conscious.
This
may be sufficient to show that natural science has a necessary tendency
to render nature intelligent; through this very tendency it becomes
nature-philosophy, which is one of the necessary basic sciences
of philosophy.[lv][55]
Light, the subject of the science of optics, the
most advanced science of Schelling's time, is of doubtful materiality
- something almost ideal. The completed theory of nature would be
that whereby the whole of nature is resolved into mind. Inanimate
nature is just immature intelligence. Nothing is concrete. All material
traces are vanishing - the passage states the theory of erosion.
To be sure, in this section of the introduction,
Schelling was merely drawing out the implications proposing that spirit
and nature are disjoined, and spirit has the higher reality, a position
he always rejected.[lvi][56]
Still, the extreme cogency with which he could put forward the description
of those consequences suggests that Schelling was keenly aware that
his only own thinking was prone to run towards accepting those claims,
and that that is why he went to the extremes he did to develop his
philosophy of identity. In his Freiheitschrift he opined that
the highest point in his whole inquiry is that there must be a Be-ing
prior to any duality whatsoever. Throughout his philosophy, he insisted
on the Spinozistic idea of the identity of nature and consciousness.
The insistence is an expression of his fear that nature was coming
forth as unreal.
The loss of identity that so concerned
Schelling is at the core of Benjamin's commentary on the auratic quality
of artworks. Even the very title of Benjamin's famous article, "The
Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproducibility" suggests Benjamin's
fundamental concerning with the self-identity of objects; but the
following passages make the proposition explicit.
To
bring things spatially and humanly "closer" is a no less passionate
inclination of today's masses than is their tendency to overcome the
uniqueness of every given [event] through the reception of its reproduction.
Every day the need grows stronger to get hold of an object as closely
as possible in the image, that is, in the likeness, in the reproduction.
And unmistakably the reproduction, as offered by illustrated magazines
and newsreels, distinguishes itself from the image. Uniqueness and
duration are as closely linked in the latter as are the transitoriness
and repeatability in the former. The prying of an object from its
shell, the destruction of its aura, is the signature of a perception
whose "sense of the sameness in the world" has increased to such a
degree that it extracts it even from the unique by means of reproduction.[lvii][57]
Or, again:
One
might subsume the eliminated element in the term 'aura' and go on
to say: that which withers in the age of mechanical reproduction is
the aura of the work of art. This is a symptomatic process whose significance
points beyond the realm of art. One might generalize by saying: the
technique of reproduction detaches the reproduced object from the
domain of tradition. In making reproductions it substitutes a plurality
of copies for a unique existence. And in permitting the reproduction
to meet the beholder or listener in his own particular situation,
it reactivates the object reproduced. These two processes lead to
a tremendous shattering of tradition which is the obverse of the contemporary
crisis and renewal of mankind."[lviii][58]
Note the language: "shattering of tradition" and
"the obverse of the . . . renewal of mankind." It is evident that
for Benjamin, the destruction of the auratic network marked the artwork
for death - or, at least, for the termination of its objective being.
As it was for Schelling, so it was for Benjamin: reproducibility,
the splitting of identity into duality (indeed even into multiplicity),
brings the curse of death on objects.
Another aspect of Schelling's later philosophy
anticipated ideas that later philosophers, including Benjamin and
Baudrillard, would adopt. Schelling's dispute with his former disciple,
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel is the stuff of legends; and differences
between the two are often described as reflecting the differences
between Hegel's more philosophically rigorous spirit and Schelling's
comparative philosophical wooliness and his frequent changes of mind.
That assessment is hardly accurate. The real basis for the difference
is that Schelling emphasized the finite facticity of absolute reason.
Schelling rejected the Hegelian principle that identifies of the rational
and the real, and even went so far as to argue that reality cannot
be derived from reason. Unmoored from any connection to the Absolute
(either the transcendent divine of Judaeo-Christian or the unmoved
mover of classical thought), reality appeared to be a domain of chaos,
lack of order, impulse and desire.
There are, then, unreasoning or irrational
powers inherent in the constitution of reality, which Schelling referred
to as "the dark will." His concept of the transience (Vergänglichkeit,
"fleetingness," perhaps "precariousness") of all things is key here,
for his later philosophy depicts that precariousness as ontologically
intimate with evil and with the absurd; Schelling recognized, in the
end, that darkness is too deeply infused in the order of reality to
be considered as mere appearance or privation. Evil possesses real,
positive force. We have already seen that Schelling characterized
the transition from infinitude to finitude as an "Abfall" ("a
fall") and an even as an "Urzufall" ("a primal accident.);
we also have seen that there is no logical necessity that would compell
one to conclude that finitude is privation, as Schelling had. Only
by evoking the idea existence as having a dual character, some notion
of existence as divided between spirit and matter, essentially between
be-ing and nonbe-ing, can one account for the structure of Schelling's
system. Thus, the real determinants are theological: there is to be
sure, a heterodox, indeed, Gnostic provenance for the metaphysics
of Hegel and Schelling.[lix][59] The
objects of nature have a material component, and matter resists all
that is dynamic, all that strives for freedom. Matter is the source
of privation; matter separates spirit from the origin.
Schelling, furthermore, explicitly likened
the transition from identity to difference in God to the process of
becoming conscious. In doing so, he developed a conception of double
existence that was to influence, inter alia, Arthur Schopenhauer,
Friedrich Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger (especially his ideas about
ontological difference), Walter Benjamin, Georg Lukács, Guy Debord
and Jean Baudrillard.
If
we now become conscious of ourselves - if light and darkness are separate
in us [note the Gnostic lexis] - then we do not go out of ourselves;
the two principles remain in us as their unity. We lose nothing of
our essence, but instead just possess ourselves now in a double form,
namely once in unity, the other time in division. So with God.[lx][60]
As the citation suggests, Schelling strived mightily
to create a strictly monistic system. Nevertheless, the consequences
of his belief that "the origin of the world of the senses can only
be thought as a complete breaking off from absoluteness, by a leap"
continue to unfold throughout Schelling's philosophy. Indeed one could
argue that the originary absolute in Schelling's metaphysics was precisely
a striving towards duality. Evidence of the tendency towards dualism
can be found in the widening of the gulf separating the differentiated
world from the realm of identity as Schelling's system evolved. Here
is one of Schelling's more extreme statements on the matter:
To
the extent that this conduit [between the individual consciousness
and the original identity] is broken, sickness is present. . . . Therefore
(1) if the conduit is broken by mood [Gefühl] then an emotional
sickness arises. (2) If the conduit is broken by intellect, stupidity..
. . (3) If the conduit is broken both by mood and by intellect, then
the consequence is the most dire, namely madness. Really, I should
have said "it arises," but "it emerges" . . . [for] the deepest level
of human spirit . . . when it is regarded in isolation from the soul
and therefore from God, is madness.[lxi][61]
Division, even as it brings forth the world of objects,
unleashes baneful forces. Nature, accordingly, is a realm permeated
by dire operations that demand sacrifice. Death, non-being, unreality,
is the ultimate issue of division. "Through death, the physical (to
the extent that it is real) and the spiritual are made one. Unblessedness
consists in the soul's inability to act as subject because of the
rebellion of the spirit, which results in the separation of the soul
from God."[lxii][62]
Total unreality - the unreality of that which has passed away - will
be the end of division, of fragmentation, of corruption. This is heritage
of Schelling's of philosophy, the legacy which spawned Baudrillard's
ideas about the precession of the simulacra, where non-being's triumph
over being will cast out all the dire forces that result from the
divide that separates beings from Be-ing - the groundless be-ing of
beings, be-ing akin to non-be-ing, will absorb Be-ing itself.
Schelling also expresses the Gnostic sentiment
that human being, as spiritual reality, abides here on earth in an
alien realm.
Something
intermediate arises in mortals, namely a visible drama, because this
presents his spiritual creations simultaneously in reality. So the
story is best regarded as a tragedy acted out on the stage of the
world's sorrows, to which they merely offer the planks, while the
subjects of the drama, that is, the leading characters on the planks,
are from a completely different world.[lxiii][63]
In Schelling's system, as so often in the Western
ontotheological tradition, the division between Be-ing and beings
led to conception that the Absolute, no matter how near, is utterly
beyond language and sensation. The idea that the Absolute is beyond
the limits of language and sensation has often led thinkers to accept
a spurious and logically invalid, but nonetheless emotionally forceful,
chain of inferences: If Be-ing is so different from the be-ing of
beings, if it is beyond sensation, indeed beyond all knowing, if it
dwells in darkness, it must be, to all intents and purposes, nothing.
As Nietzsche's philosophy makes clear, the conviction that the absolute
Be-ing is really Nothing (the idea that God is dead) has been responsible
for the conclusion that beings themselves are unreal. Thus, the disconnection
of beings from Be-ing, the ideas that beings do not make manifest
the charity of Be-ing (which disconnection from Be-ing renders wholly
unknowable) results in the conviction that Be-ing is Nothingness,
and belief in the Nothingness of Be-ing undermines trust in the reality
of beings. Thus the idea of the disconnection of beings from Be-ing,
the idea that existence is bifurcated and that beings inhabit a realm
cut off from Be-ing results in the slaying of Be-ing by beings - through
which act through which they themselves come into the unreality of
death. And everywhere that these ideas were adopted, they continued,
unknowingly, to steer thinkers toward the view that objective representations
are illusory.
What the Romantics bequeathed us, finally,
was a metaphysical structure the conceptual basis that has its conceptual
basis in Gnosticism. This provenance of this structure soon was forgotten,
but the structure itself continued to shape metaphysical thinking
for the next hundred years and more. It is a key aspect of Benjamin's
writing. Near the end of The Origin of the German Tragic Drama,
Benjamin decries the spiritualizing, redemptionist tropes that conclude
so many of the dramas of the German Barock era, that sweep away the
objectivity of the real world; in doing so, Benjamin alleged, they
lose everything that was most their own.
"Mit
Weinen streuten wir den Samen in die Brachen / und giegen trauig aus"
Allegory goes away empty handed. Evil as such, which is cherished
as enduring profundity, exists only in allegory, is nothing other
than allegory . . . The absolute vices, as exemplified by tyrants
and intriguers, are allegories. They are not real, and that which
they represent, they possess only in the subjective view of melancholy;
they are this view, which is destroyed by its own offspring because
they only signify its blindness. They point to the absolutely subjective
pensiveness to which they own their existence. By its allegorical
form, evil as such reveals itself to be a subjective phenomenon. The
enormous, anti-artistic subjectivity of the baroque converges here
with the theological essence of the subjective.
Benjamin then went on to acknowledges that the proposition
that evil has objective reality contradicts a central principle of
the First Covenant:
The
Bible introduces evil in the concept of knowledge. The serpent's promise
to the first men was to make them "knowing both good and evil." But
it is said of God after the creation: "And God saw everything that
he had made, and, behold it was very good." Knowledge of evil therefore
has no object. There is no evil in the world. It arises in man himself,
with the desire for knowledge, or rather for judgment. Knowledge of
good, as knowledge, is secondary. It ensues from practice. Knowledge
of evil - as knowledge this is primary. It ensues from contemplation.
Knowledge of good and evil is, then, the opposite of all factual knowledge.
Related as it is to the depths of the subjective, it is basically
only knowledge of evil. It is 'nonsense' in the profound sense in
which Kierkegaard conceived the word. This knowledge, the triumph
of subjectivity and the onset of an arbitrary rule over things, is
the origin of all allegorical contemplation.[lxiv][64]
In the form in which the German Romantics
bequeathed it to us, the fateful structure has the following character.
Being comes from a primal absolute whose nature is dynamism, movement,
energy, productivity. That Absolute Be-ing divides and that division
sets one aspect of Be-ing against the the other. The reason that division
sets the divided parts against one another is that, in being divided,
each part relinquishes (at least in some measure) its relation to
the Absolute, so each becomes the Other for the other - in emerging
as divided being, the inner nature of each distinguished part becomes
dependent on its relation to something beyond itself, and this dependence
on the other renders each vulnerable. A relationship of mutual dependency
develops between the elements that issue from the Absolute, and that
mutual dependency leads them to turn both against one one another
and against the source of their be-ing In the Hegelian version of
this narrative, as an example, nature is first set over against the
Absolute-in-itself, as the Absolute divides itself into the an
sich and the für sich. Then the für sich turns against
the an sich, intrudes into its inner recesses, and operates
it as though by remote control. The fateful structure arises within
the dynamic that is set in motion as the Absolute becomes divided.
The way of understanding the erosion of
reality became fundamental to twentieth-century French thought: it
is the core of Kojčve's reading of the Master-Slave section of Hegel's
Die Phänomenologie des Geistes, the enormous influence of which
on post-war French philosophy has been well noted.[lxv][65] It also
provided the ground work for Jean-Paul Sartre ideas about division
between the en-soi and the pour-soi and about "the situation"
as "facticity," i.e., the given.[lxvi][66] Lukács
wrote of the same dynamic when, attempting to renew Marxist after
the events of 1956 had exposed the bankruptcy of Soviet style "Marxism,"
he turned to Marx' Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844
and mined from them the ideas of objectification and alienation. Thus,
in "Dialectical Materialism" Lukács described how, through revolutionary
praxis, the alienated person could overcome self-fragmentation and
emerge as the "total person," reconciled with the self and with the
totality of Nature and human being.[lxvii][67]
Lukács also developed a concept of the proletariat as fused "subject-object"
- as both the agent and the object of history; this concept is reminiscent
of Schelling's exposition of the Absolute as the productivity of the
fused "subject-object." In arguing for a purely proletarian revolution,
Lukács asserted that proletariat would become the universal subject
of history; it would be seen as "the identical subject-object of the
real history of mankind."
For his part, Benjamin derived his ideas
about the relative unreality of particulars in part from his studies
of the Kabala's emantionist metaphysics - though, of course, he worked
out his analysis of phantasmagoria by deliberating on the modern experience
of urban life. His efforts to decipher of modern urban experience
led him to consider the modern metropolis as the site of misrecognition
and external compulsion, as demanding constant submission to technological
realities; the parade of novelties, exhibitions, monuments, and commodities
that constituted the modern experience of urban life was nothing less
than phantasmagoric. Only the experience of shock, like that awakens
the dream drom dream, could call us out of that phantasmagoria.
Out of his deliberations on modern urban
experience (and especially of the unpredictable accolation of particulars
that is one's everyday experience of the metropolis), Benjamin evolved
his notion of the constellation. That evolution, however, was foreshadowed
in his idea of allegory, an idea he discussed in his early, important
text, The Origins of German Tragic Drama. That work used the
concept of allegory to provide a structure for understanding the lability
of signification and a context for deliberating on ways that the
shapelessness of materials can take on an eternally mutable shape.
Allegory, Benjamin pointed out, affords the possibility of endless
substitution of disparate particulars; Benjamin provided a metaphysical
explanation of the conditions that made possible this substitutability,
an explanation that relies on that sense of the connectedness of beings
whicht grounds Benjamin's entire philosophy: that things and occurrences
stand next to one another is not without significance, for beings
refer to one another. Benjamin recognized, surely, that that conviction
has scholastic roots and was traditionally used to explain the manner
in which material reality is linked to a supersensible, spiritual
reality. This is the background of Benjamin's conviction that allegory
is capable of providing every individual detail with symbolic properties.
And the concept of allegory helped found Benjamin's ideas about language,
and governed his analysis of the manner in which language presents
beings while transforming their meaning. It provided the basis for
understanding how novelty continually arises from the permutations
of a fixed set of terms, and how new being arises from novel juxtapositions
of particulars. The explanation would prove influential.
Benjamin connected the phantasmagoric to
death, just as the German Romantic philosophers associated division,
opposition, and unreality with death. Benjamin's also associated these
terms in his many references to ghosts, to the phenomenon of haunting
and to his description of the self coming forth as another in photography.[lxviii][68]
Yet, Benjamin also pointed out in the Origin of German Tragic Drama,
that be-ing is the force to imprint, and that recognition raises for
him the troubling possibility that there is no self that is not exhibited.
However, to exhibit the self always entails a loss, for every presentation
of the self is an alienation, a determination, a restriction, a partial
view (constructed to be theorized). This is the tragedy of the self's
relation to the other. One can discern that association as well in
Benjamin's insistence that the past constitutes the transcendental
conditions for what occurs in the here and now. For, by averring that
the past is alive in the present, Benjamin offered an image of the
realm of contingency as a domain in which life and death are one -
an image of a domain of lifedeath similar to that which Schelling's
philosophy offers.
We may well ask what phenomenological conditions
led to the sense that reality had been eroded, that it had dissolved
into the phantasmagoric. We have seen that German Romantic thought
was struck with the fact that in the dialectic between the subject
and the object, the inner being of each term is defined by its relation
to the other; another way to consider this dialectical relation is
to say that what is most near also belongs to - or, by extension,
can be identified with - what is beyond. This identification was often
made the central issue of the dialectic (as it often is the writings
of Walter Benjamin and that Hegelian psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan),
and when it was, the relation between the two terms was seen a relation
that develops through the self's coming forth as an other. Benjamin
was an heir to this idea, and so Benjamin developed similar ideas
about the imbrication of proximity and distance.
The topic of proximity became a principal
issue of Benjamin's thought, and he dealt with many of its aspects.
Benjamin's friends and colleagues, Berthold Brecht and Theodor Adorno,
warned against the collapse of the distance between a spectator and
the spectacle. Adorno pointed that the technological will to mastery
plays a role in the process that collapses the distance between the
spectator and spectacle. His example of the dangers of collapsing
that distance was the Wagnerian idea of the Gesammtkunstwerk:
Wagner, Adorno argued, used rational means to formulate effects that
induce a delirious phantasmagoric state in the listener/viewer. The
Gesammtkunstwerk submerges the listener/viewer in an ocean
of sounds and images. Adorno denounced this effect in terms familiar
from Schelling's ruminations on the phantasmagoria of particulars,
for he depicted the power of the Gesammtkunstwerk as a dire
force, as the dangerous other side of technological wonder, an "intoxication
of technology." Technology thus becomes the enemy of consciousness.
Enthusiasm for technology can be seen as product of a Faustian pact
with the devil, just as Spengler had suggested.
The distance that formerly had precluded
the intoxicating effects of immersion in the phantasmagoria spanned
two dimensions, one psychical and one physical. Benjamin recognized
that photography and film had destroyed that distance, for the camera
operator, whom Benjamin comparee to a surgeon who "penetrates deeply
into its [reality's] web," zooms in so as to "pry an object from its
shell." Several early film theorists, including Benjamin's colleague,
Siegfried Kracauer, celebrated the ability of the camera to penetrate
reality. Dziga Vertov's film, A Man with the Movie Camera,
similarly celebrates the camera's capacity to penetrate reality -
the film extols the camera's superiority over human vision, which
results from ability to go anywhere to obtain a close-up of any object.
But Benjamin did not concur - at least not wholly - with the Kracauer
and Vertov in celebrating the camera's capacity to bring what is distant
exceedingly close. To the contrary, he decried the potentially deleterious
consequences: close-ups, he explained, satisfy the desires of the
masses "to bring things 'closer' spatially and humanly," "to get hold
of an object at very close range."
The use of a close-up causes us to disregard
scale and emplacement - that is, to ignore the actual physical situation
to which events and objects belong and which are a part of an object's
unique being.[lxix][69]
Throughout his commentary on emplacement, Foucault stressed that the
system of oppositions that structured the space of emplacement constitutes
a horizon of meaning for the objects that space contained. Foucault
even pointed out that in the medieval period assigned anything -
an object, event, or idea - that appears out of place in an
"artificial" location in order to secure its place in the medieval
world and imaginary. Thus, even incongruous events are accorded a
place in a system of that makes them comprehensible. I, too, am using
the term to suggest the horizon of meaning which results from the
place that the object occupies within a system of objects and meanings.
Hence, the use of a close-up results in our discarding the unique
and meaningful situation to which events and objects belong. As photographs
of various events and various objects were brought together in a single
picture magazine or a film newsreel, the significant differences between
them, resulting from the different situations (emplacement), are levelled.
Thus Benjamin concludes that the forms which comply with the demands
of mass democracy engender an impression "the universal equality of
things."
The destruction of distance evokes an almost
paradoxical feeling feeling that combines remoteness and detachment.
That feeling is the result of the anaesthetizing effects of immersion
in the phantasmagoria. The image-world so positions us that we do
not feel ourselves to be agents. Rather the image-flow determines
our affects, and nothing we can do can alter the course of that inevitable
flow. Because we cannot change it, or the phenomena it comprises,
they seem remote, even though, in fact, they have never been so near.
This sensation which evokes a combination
of proximity and distance is a characteristic sensation of the era
of modernity. Heidegger too commented on the paradoxical combination
of nearness and remoteness in his 1947 essay, "Das Ding" ("The Thing").
Man
puts the largest expanses behind him in the shortest time. He puts
the greatest distances behind himself and thereby brings everything
before them at the shortest range. Yet the rushed abolition of all
remoteness brings no closeness; for closeness does not consist in
the reduction of distance. What is least removed from us in terms
of expanse, through the image in film or though sound in radio, can
still remain remote. What in terms of expanse is unimaginably far
removed, can be very close to us. Reduced distance is not in itself
closeness. Nor is great distance remoteness.[lxx][70]
This peculiar amalgam of distance and closeness
so characteristic of photography marks the destruction of the familiar
spatial coordinates. Thus, just as the speed of modern life irretrievably
altered our perception of time, the invention of the photographic
close-up destroyed our familiar conception of space. It brought objects
close, thus obliterating space; at the same time by subjugating us
to them, it elevated them to the remote domain of the beyond. This
dialectic of proximity and distance has structural similarity with
that relation which is a principal topic of German Romantic thought,
the relation between self and other in which the inner being of each
depends on its outward relation to the other - the self corresponds
to proximity, the other corresponds to distance.[lxxi][71]
A similar amalgam of remoteness and intimacy was the defining feature
of aura for Benjamin, which at one point he defines as the "singular
phenomenon of a distance however close it may be."[lxxii][72]
Benjamin exerted a considerable influenced
on Jean Baudrillard - indeed among all the descendants of German Romanticism
that shaped Baudrillard's thought (among whom, of course, Friedrich
Nietzsche figures prominently), it is Walter Benjamin who exerted
the greatest influence. Baudrillard's ideas on hyperreality work out
the implications of Benjamin's ideas on reproducibility, but omitted
any sense of the ontological justification for the be-ing of beings.
Benjamin's famous article, "The Work of Art in an Era of Technical
Reproducibility" had analyzed the ontological consequences of the
technological development that made it possible to reproduce everything
mechanically. Objects lost their uniqueness, and one of the consequences
of this loss of uniqueness was the elimination of the aura. Reproduction
- doubling - troubled Benjamin's famous essay - evidence of this is
to be seen in his remarks on ghosts and the phenomenon of haunting,
on the dopplegänger, the self's coming to be for as the other (which
is a theme of his writings on photographic portraiture) etc.,
remarks that, to be sure, relate to his ideas on the phantasmagoria.
A companion concept, reproducibility, troubles Baudrillard's writings
on art, and issues in his melancholy ideas on hyperreality.
The destruction of the physical and psychical
distance between the subject and the object of perception is a problematic
central to Paul Virilio's writing. Virilio alleges that telecommunication
that eradicates temporal extension from the transmission of messages
and images and that interactive computer technologies decenter urban
or lived space; these transformations of space constitute a threat
as they dissolve previous configurations of experience and render
space virtual. Space and time takes on new modalities as previous
configurations of space and time are replaced by light-time (i.e.
the time of the speed of light) and a new 'lumiocentrism' (5 f. and
14 f.), in which the instantaneous flow of information breaks up all
previous configurations of time and space.[lxxiii][73]
Lumiocentrism requires new concepts to describe the processes of the
emergent worlds of technological experience.
While both natural perception and painting
had maintained a distance from the represented object, Virilio suggests,
the new technologies of mass reproduction do not. The effects of that
destruction have become especially evident in the electronic media
of telepresence. By collapsing physical distances, the technologies
of mass reproducibility uproot those familiar patterns of perception
which were the groundwork of our culture and politics. Virilio encapsulates
the differences between the two perceptual / political regimes in
his contrast between "Small Optics" and "Big Optics."
Small Optics is the optics of human vision, painting and film; Big
Optics is the optics of the era of real-time electronic transmission
of information, "the active optics of time passing at the speed of
light." The key science for Small Optics was the science of geometric
optics (now by and large subsumed in the science of affine transformations);
the key science for Big Optics is kinematics. The shift from Small
Optics to Big Optics results from a change in nature of space. Distance,
and so space, relates to the minimal time it takes for an object to
traverse a given span. In the era of Small Optics the most significant
bodies were actual physical bodies, so the crucial traversal times
were those of real objects, but in the era of Big Optics, the most
significant objects are units of information, so the crucial traversal
times are those of data objects. Accordingly, in the era of Big Optics,
distances, and space, have shrunk. While Small Optics involved distinctions
between near and far, between an object and a horizon against which
the object is set, Big Optics has erased those distinctions, since
information from any point can be transmitted with the same speed.
Virilio argues that developments in science
and technology have obliterated both modern and common sense views
of the world, produced new objects and created a new form of space
that cannot be explained by modernity's conceptual schemes. Explorations
in the 'physics of the infinitesimally small' and the cosmological
speculations on outer space have created novelties and puzzles that
brought the facts of perception and the realm of experience into question,
even while they have discovered/made reference to novel, unperceived,
and imperceptible entities, which confound common sense and the scientific
schemes of modernity. Furthermore, new technologies are producing
both new objects (i.e. cyberspace, virtual reality, etc.) and new
modes of perception and representation (i.e. fractal geometry, chaos
and complexity theory, computer_generated representations of external
and internal realities, etc.) that themselves require new modes of
thought and cognition.
These transformations of perceptual and
representational modalities began with the development of microscopes
and telescopes, were given added impetus by the invention of cinematography
that captured motion and phenomena not visible to the naked eye, and
have been further stimulated by the technologies of virtuality. Virilio
mourns the loss of the object of ocular perception that occurred as
a result of the technological changes. He decries the displacement
of the dimension of direct observation and common sense effected by
the emergence of technological vision and representation, and laments
thus the loss of the materiality and concreteness of the objects of
perception, constituting the realm of appearance and lived experience.
In sum, Virilio mourns the loss of the phenomenological dimension
that privileged lived experience. Virilio was much influenced by phenomenology,
and he roots his thought in concrete experience of objects, people,
and processes in the observed and experienced worlds of everyday life
and the natural and social worlds. For him, the new technological
worlds break with with ordinary experience and, in doing so, shift
the locus of truth, meaning, and validity to an abstract and enigmatic
virtual realm.
Compared with Benjamin's ideas on photography,
Virilio's ideas about Big Optics propound a more radical analysis
of the new technologies' powers to destroy the crucial sense of emplacement.
While Benjamin had analyzed how photography and film uprooted every
object from its original setting, Virilio inquires into the manner
in which post-industrial technologies have eliminated the dimension
of space, as every point on Earth now is instantly accessible from
any other point on Earth. The historical period that separates Benjamin
from Virilio is characterized by a progressive diminution both of
the groundedness of human being and the horizon of transcendence:
In 1936, Benjamin included amongst what is natural for human perception
only natural scenes and paintings, and argued that photography and
film, because they had destroyed psychic distance by making it possible
to bring everything equally close, had eroded the aura that once surrounded
images; half a century later, Virilio charted an even more pernicious
transformation in the technologies of vision. If photography and film
represented, for Benjamin, an alien imposition on human vision, Virilio
sees the film image as essentially continuous with our natural sight,
since it is based on geometric optics. In his view, the historical
break between film and telecommunication, between the Small Optics
of painting, photography and film and the Big Optics of telecommunications
and the electronic media, is more complete, and has more far-reaching
effects, than that marked by the transformation of distance with the
advent of photographic and cinematographic technologies which allowed
the production of close-ups.
The half century between Benjamin and Virilio's
times also saw an increasing eradication of the traditional sense
of physical space and matter. Through this, mobile signs - maps, we
might call them - acceded to priority over the actual objects and
relations: as Benjamin (and Marx) foretold, capitalism volatized and
rendered labile that all that is solid, all that is grounded. For
capitalism strives to clear away whatever might impede circulation
- and whatever is truly singular (including objects surrounded by
an aura) is not really available for exchange. Electronic communications
exaggerate these effects of capitalism, effects that Charles Baudelaire
had described in the middle of the nineteenth century. In Le peintre
de la vie moderne, he noted that "the daily metamorphosis of exterior
things . . . demands from the artist an equal velocity of execution."[lxxiv][74] Thus,
electronic communication makes instantaneous the process by which
objects are turned into signs. Furthermore, in contrast to photography,
whose products remain fixed once they are printed, digital representation
makes every image inherently mutable and forever modifiable. Because
it can in effect transport the viewer to any location that can be
represented on the electronic screen, and because it allows one to
alter in real time the material reality that one sees via "tele-vision,"
telepresence volatizes physical objects themselves, by eradicating
the space of action.
However, action-at-distance, and action
through tele-vision, defies traditional ontology's conception of identity
- inasmuch as such action-at-a distance seemingly demands that the
object be both proximate and distant, both "here" and "there." Thus
tele-action upsets our assumption about the nature of event, specifically
our assumption that an event must occupy a restricted patch of spacetime.
Telemedia exacerbate the effects of capitalist economics, by contributing
to the forces that elevates the sign over the object since it allows
for the manipulation of objects through these signs.
All in all, the electronic media have expanded
the effect of photograph that Benjamin had observed, that of destroying
the sense of objects' emplacement. This destruction of environing
space has deleterious consequences. We have been locked up in a flattened
out world, for objects have become bereft of a horizon that might
endow objects with a depth, with a richness of meaning. The Earth
has become a prison: witness "the progressive derealization of the
terrestrial horizon, . . . resulting in an impending primacy of real
time perspective of undulatory optics over real space of the linear
geometrical optics of the Quattrocento." Virilio states.
Virilio also laments the destruction of
distance and the vastness of natural space which guaranteed a delay
between events and our reactions, a delay that gives us time for reflection.
The advent, first, of film, then of telecommunication, and finally
of telepresence mark the progressive diminution - and, in the end,
the complete elimination - of one of fundamental conditions of human
perception, viz, the distance between the subject who is seeing
and the object being seen. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Hélčne Cixous and
Luce Irigaray represent a recent tendency that has denigrated the
role of psychical distance, arguing that distance becomes responsible
for creating the gap between the spectator and spectacle - a gap that
separates subject from object, that raises the subject above the object
and installs the subject in the position of mastery. Against all that
led to the contemporary celebration of touch as involving a chiasmatic
relation between the toucher and the touched, Benjamin (though with
significantly more reservations) and Virilio extol the salutary effects
of distance.[lxxv][75]But
notice, too, that utensils exhibit that strange amalgam of proximity
and distance that is one of Benjamin's favorite themes. For Benjamin
and Virilio, distance preserves the aura of an object, its position
in the world, while the capacity to bring all things close utterly
destroys the material order by rendering our notions about space
meaningless.[lxxvi][76]
Virilio is, famously, a theorist of speed,
and his notions about speed relate to his ideas about Big Optics.
Speed, like Big Optics, has threatened our sense of reality. For it
is clear to Virilio that a certain measure of slowness or deliberation,
as well as a certain quantum of distance are necessary for us to sense
the coherence of real. That sense of deliberation, and its correlative,
a sense of (extended) duration has salutary effects in the overcoming
the feeling that reality has volatilized.[lxxvii][77] The
inauguration of the regime of Big Optics marked the beginning of real
time politics, the politics of instant reactions to the events transmitted
with the speed of light. Such a regime requires instantaneous response,
response at a speed that can only be efficiently handled by computers;
thus, person-to-person exchanges are replaced with exchanges between
machines.
Of course, speed and aggression are intimately
related - and not the least among the reasons for that association
is speed's hostility to contemplation. Virilio's analysis of aggression
arises from the tension of dialectical relation between the an
sich and the für sich, between self and the alienated self,
which, having been reified, is experienced as the other. The French
Situationist, Raoul Vaneigem, earlier offered similar ideas, in his
commentary on what, astonishingly, he calls "free play":
At
the opposite extreme from absolute identification is a particular
way of putting a distance between the role and one's self, a way of
establishing a zone of free play. This zone is a breeding place of
attitudes disruptive of the spectacular order. Nobody is ever completely
swallowed up by a role. Even turned on its head, the will to live
retains a potential for violence always capable of carrying the individual
away from the path laid down for him. One fine morning, the faithful
lackey, who has hitherto identified completely with his master, leaps
on his oppressor and slits his throat. For he has reached that point
where his right to bite like a dog has finally aroused his desire
to strike back like a human being. Diderot has described this moment
well in Rameau's Nephew _ and the case of the Papin sisters
illustrates it even better.[lxxviii][78]
One again, we discern in this passage that
peculiar dialectic by which the mirror world turns against that which
it mirrors; and we could find passages in the writings in Guy Debord
and Jean Baudrillard that make the same point. In this passage, too,
that dialectic sets in motion the process we observed in the writings
of German Romantics. But the similarities only go so far - what distinguishes
the views of such post-Nietzscheans as Vaneigem, Debord and Baudrillard
from Schelling and Hegel's ideas on the topic of the revenge of the
alienated realm is that for the Post-Nietzscheans, the projections
which constitute the für sich are acknowledged as appearing
groundless, empty, phantasmal. Here is Vaneigem again, pronouncing
on the madness of these delusory projections/representations.
There
is no such thing as mental illness. It is merely a convenient label
for grouping and isolating cases where identification has not occurred
properly. Those whom Power can neither govern nor kill, it taxes with
madness. The category includes extremists and megalomaniacs of the
role, as well as those who deride roles or refuse them. It is only
the isolation of such individuals which condemns them, however. Let
a General identify with France, with the support of millions of voters,
and an opposition immediately springs up which seriously seeks to
rival him in his lunacy. Horbiger's attempt to invent a Nazi physics
met with a similar kind of success. General Walker was taken seriously
when he drew a distinction between superior, white, divine and capitalist
man on the one hand, and black, demoniacal, communist man on the other.
Franco would meditate devoutly and beg God for guidance in oppressing
Spain. Everywhere in the world are leaders whose cold frenzy lends
substance to the thesis that man is a machine for ruling. True madness
is a function not of isolation but of identification.
Reality has become simply a social consensus. De
Gaulle claims to be France, and millions agree - so that becomes a
reality of Power. Another person makes a similar claim, but is greeted
with nothing but disbelief, and is condemned to the asylum. Not only
that, but the one who succeeds in convincing people that he is their
leader provokes opposition within the same register as his power exists,
that is the register of delusion, of madness. So it is a no-win game
- go along with it, and one is mad, oppose it, and one is still made.
What accounts for this transformation,
by which the für sich comes to seem illusory, phantasmal, dreamlike,
even the stuff of madness? We have already gone a distance in formulating
an explanation. In the writings of Benjamin, Debord, Vaneigem and
(mutatis mutandis) Baudrillard productive forces have a status
similar in some respects to that which the Absolute has in Schelling's
thought: like Schelling's Absolute, they are accorded primacy; and
like Schelling's Absolute their essence is that of a productivity.
And what is most important in this comparison, these forces, like
Schelling's Absolute produce elements that have a relationship of
mutual dependency on one another (recall Schelling's assertion, in
Philosophie und Religion, that "the origin of no finite things
leads immediately back to the infinite, it can instead only be grasped
via the sequence of causes and which, which is, though itself endless,
whose law has therefore not a positive but merely a negative meaning").
And that mutual dependency leads them to turn both against one another
and against the source of their be-ing. It is the primacy of the productive
energy that here is at issue: and thinking about that primacy carries
us back to him who staked the original claim that material forces
of production are responsible for shaping historical realities, that
is to Karl Marx.
Marx's philosophical system was an inversion
of Hegel's - where Hegel had put Concept, Marx would put matter. Like
Schelling and Hegel's philosophy, Marx's writings describe the productive
forces as the primary reality, and that which they produce as a secondary
reality. But there is a more important similarity: as Schelling and
Hegel did, Marx came to the conclusion that there is a symmetrical
relation between the two elements that issue from the productivity
that is the ontological basis of their be-ing - between, that is,
the subject/producer and the object. Indeed Marx' materialism ensures
that the relation between the producer and the object would have be
symmetrical.[lxxix][79] Furthermore,
because, like the relation between Subject and Object in Fichte, Schelling
and Hegel's philosophies, the relation between producer and object
is one of mutual dependency, that relation has an eristic character
- its Hegelian basis required Marx' philosophy to assert that labour
must struggle to extract from matter what it requires and the exchange
value that commodities take on will turn against the labourer and
eventually even against the labour process itself.
We have seen this dynamic before: A primal
productivity brings forth elements that enter into a relationship
of mutual dependency, and that lead them to turn both against one
another and against the source of their being. A hypostatization of
Be-ing results, through which the status of Be-ing is reduced to that
of the be-ing of beings. To state the point in a more Baudrillardian
fashion. A hypostatization occurs which results in beings absorbing
Be-ing. The consequences of this for any philosophy that moves within
the orbit of ontotheology (and almost all Western philosophy does)
is the loss of reality, for in ontotheology, Be-ing is the ontological
basis of the be-ing of beings, and reducing Be-ing to the equivalent
of the be-ing of beings results in the all be-ing losing its ground.
We can discern the consequences of onto-theology
in Debord's writings just as clearly as in Marx'. Debord described
the spectacle as the constantly changing, self_organizing and self_sustaining
expression of the modern form of production (a form of production
quite different from the capitalist form), a massive and complex apparatus
which serves to perpetuate that false consciousness which necessary
to make the modern (capitalist) form of social organization palatable
to the general population.[lxxx][80] All
readers will know the impasse to which such ideas have led: here,
as an example of the legacy of onto-theology, is Baudrillard on "hyperreality"
From
medium to medium, the real is volatilized, becoming an allegory of
death. But it is also, in a sense, reinforced through its own destruction.
It becomes reality for its own sake, the fetishism of the lost
object: no longer the object of representation, but the ecstasy of
denial and of its own ritual extermination: the hyperreal. . . . The
hyperreal . . . manages to efface even this contradiction between
the real and the imaginary. Unreality no longer resides in the dream
or fantasy, or in the beyond, but in the real's hallucinatory resemblance
to itself.[lxxxi][81]
Baudrillard
gives voice to the same feeling that Schelling had expressed more
than a century earlier, the sense that nature (in Baudrillard's system,
implosion already has converted that realm into that is "no longer
nature") is haunted by dire forces, that it is the realm of death.[lxxxii][82] Similarly
Baudrillard's "principle of Evil . . . expressed in the cunning genius
of the object, . . . its victorious strategy over the subject" is
the same principle of evil implicit in German Romantic philosophy
(in, for example, Hegel's principle of the cunning genius of history),
a principle that German Romantic derived from Gnosticism: the origin
of all that is baneful is the division that sets nature over against
the subject, for that division establishes the condition for nature
to turn against the subject - and what is worse, since the primal
productivity and its products all have the similar ontological status
(Be-ing has been brought within the realm of beings), it sets the
stage, for the divided elements to turn not only against one another
but also against that which produced them..[lxxxiii][83]
Baudrillard
makes explicit the role that the double plays in his theories regarding
hyperreality explicit - he points out that in his thinking, as in
German Romantic thought, the double is the source of malfeasance.
It
is precisely when it appears most truthful, most faithful and most
in conformity to reality that the image is most diabolical . . ..
It is in its resemblance, not only analogical but technological, that
the image is most immoral and most perverse.
The
appearance of the mirror introduced into the world of perception an
ironical effect of trompe-l'oeil, and we know what malefice
was attached to the appearance of doubles. But this is also true of
all the images which surround us: in general they are analysed according
to their value as representations, as media of presence and meaning.
The immense majority of present day photographic, cinematic and television
images are thought to bear witness to the world with a naive resembance
and touching fidelity. We have spontaneous confidence in their realism.
We are wrong. They only seem to resemble reality, events, faces. Or
rather, they really do conform, but their conformity itself is diabolical.[lxxxiv][84]
This is the dynamic that produces Baudrillard's
analysis of the conversion of nature into "no longer nature." What
caused it this conversion, Baudrillard suggests, was that the Transcendental
Signifier lost its depth of reference and so could no longer guarantee
the referential depth of any sign. Thus, the entire semiotic system
became ungrounded - meaning no longer entailed reference to an extra-systematic
element, for there was no point de capiton to tack the signifier
to extra-systematic reality; the map represents a purely imaginary
terrain, without reality, and all interpretations of anything (distance,
height, speed, etc) that are arrived at on the basis of information
the map provides are simply additional imaginary constructs erected
on the back of an already imaginary construct. Meaning has been converted
to endless deferral of reference from sign to sign, without purchase
on anything non-semantic element. In the absence of any point de
capiton to tack the interpretation (the sign) to reality, each
interpretation is as good as any other. Possible realities proliferate,
just as they do in the Many Worlds Interpretation of quantum mechanics.[lxxxv][85]
One could put the idea in another way,
and point out that the fatal step is taken when the transcendent pole
of experience was conceived as being like the beings that make up
the immanent pole. This hypostatization of Be-ing results in the reduction
of the status of Be-ing to the be-ing of beings; that is to say, beings
absorb Be-ing. Be-ing becomes for understanding simply one more being
amongst others, one whose existence is contingent and open to questions
concerning its nature and value, if it is acknowledged at all. But
in theological systems (and Western philosophy from the time of Plato
has been an onto-theology) Be-ing provides the ontological justification
of the be-ing of beings, and reducing Be-ing first to the equivalent
of the be-ing of beings, and then to the equivalent, quite simply,
of beings themselves, results in the all be-ing losing its ground.
Baudrillard recognizes the consequences for ontotheological system
entailed in likening Be-ing to the be-ing of beings, or even to beings
themselves..
.
Thus
perhaps at stake has always been the murderous capacity of images,
murderers of the real, murderers of their own model, as the Byzantine
icons could murder the divine identity. To this murderous capacity
is opposed the dialectical capacity of representations as a visible
and intelligible mediation of the Real. All of Western faith and good
faith was engaged in this wager on representation: That a sign could
refer to the depth of meaning, that a sign could exchange for meaning,
and that something could guarantee this exchange - God, of course.
But what if God himself can be simulated, that is to say, reduced
to the signs which attest his existence? Then the whole system becomes
weightless, it is no longer anything but a gigantic simulacrum - not
unreal, but a simulacrum, never again exchanging for what is real,
but exchanging in itself, in an uninterrupted circuit without reference
or circumference.[lxxxvi][86]
The tendency ultimately to conceive Be-ing as having
the same status as the be-ing of beings was the fatal step that the
German Romantics took and the reason they took it was they first conceived
of Be-ing as bringing forth ontologically differentiated elements,
and then (difference's coming out of unity being difficult to fathom)
diverted their attention away from the difference between Be-ing and
be-ing of beings. That diversion allowed them to depict the opposition
between beings and Be-ing as being like the opposition between the
differentiated parts that came forth from Be-ing, as having a symmetrical
form (for it commits that crucial error which leads to the erosion
of reality, viz., the reduction of be-ing to presence). Baudrillard
followed in the footsteps of Jena Romantics, developing ideas about
the erosion of reality that have surprising similarity to ideas first
expounded by German Romantic thinkers (and especially to ideas that
Schelling expounded). In fact, the basics of his thought follow a
pattern theirs established.
Baudrillard describes the very same dynamic
that the German Romantics did, of the population of the double world
of the mirror turning against and destroying that from which it arises:
More
generally, the image is interesting not only in its role as reflection,
mirror, representation of, and counterpart to, the real, but also
when it begins to contaminate reality and to model it, when it only
conforms to reality the better to distort it, or better still: when
it appropriates reality for its own ends, when it anticipates it to
the point that the real no longer has time to be produced as such.
[lxxxvii][87]
The double first mirrors, then attacks,
and ends by taking over and absorbing that which it doubles: this
Baudrillardian story is familiar from Jena Romanticism. The other
tale about the double that Jena Romanticism tells is the tale of how
twins emerged from an common source, then became locked in struggle
with one another which eventually spread, as the twins, who were once
sworn enemies, began to collude as, together, they turned against
that one who gave birth to them. Baudrillard recounts that tale as
well. l